Rubbing One Out: Defining Metasexual Violence of Objectification Through Nonconsensual Masturbation
A SCHOLARLY PAPER FROM THE GRIEVANCE STUDIES PROJECT
Summary
In the name of Lisa A. Jones, Ph.D. (fictitious) of the (fictitious) Feminist Activist Collective for Truth (FACT) by Peter Boghossian, James Lindsay, and Helen Pluckrose.
Discipline/subdiscipline: feminist studies
Summary: When a man privately masturbates while fantasizing about a woman who has not given him permission to do so, or while fantasizing about her in ways she hasn’t consented to, he has committed “metasexual” violence against her, even if she never finds out. “Metasexual” violence is described as a kind of nonphysical sexual violence that causes depersonalization of the woman by sexually objectifying her and making her a kind of mental prop used to facilitate male orgasm.
Purpose: The definition of sexual violence can be expanded into thought crimes.
Notes on Status: Peer reviewed and rejected by Sociological Theory
Selected Reviewer Comments:
“One aspect I thought about was the extent to which metasexual violence, and non- consensual masturbation specifically, introduces uncertainty into all relationships. It is not possible for women to know if a man has masturbated while thinking about them, and I think it might be possible to get theoretical leverage out of this “unknowable” aspect of metasexual violence.” -Reviewer 1, Sociological Theory
“I was also trying to think through examples of how this theoretical argument has implications in romantic consensual relationships. Through the paper, I was thinking about the rise of sexting and consensual pornographic selfies between couples, and how to situate it in your argument. I think this is interesting because you could argue that even if these pictures are shared and contained within a consensual private relationship, the pictures themselves are a reaction to the idea that the man may be thinking about another woman while masturbating. The entire industry of boudoir photography, where women sometimes have erotic pictures taken for their significant other before deploying overseas in the military for example, is implicitly a way of saying, “if you’re going to masturbate, it might as well be to me.” Essentially, even in consensual monogamous relationships, masturbatory fantasies might create some level of coercion for women. You mention this theme on page 21 in terms of the consumption of non-consensual digital media as metasexual-rape, but I think it is interesting to think through these potentially more subtle consensual but coercive elements as well.” -Reviewer 1, Sociological Theory
Contents:
Abstract
Rubbing One Out: Defining Metasexual Violence of Objectification Through Nonconsensual Masturbation
Sexual Injury, Objectification, and Rape Culture
Male Masturbation as Symbolic, Discursive, and Gender Violence
Symbolic Violence
Discursive Violence
Gender Violence
Metasexual Violence
Concluding Remarks
References
Reviewer Comments
Abstract
The psychological harms attendant to the sexual objectification of women are well-documented throughout the theoretical and empirical literature, but to date there is very little discussion on whether and when these harms and the routine behaviors that create them constitute a form of violence against women. By drawing upon empirical studies of psychological harms of objectification, especially through depersonalization, and exploring several veins of theoretical literature on nonphysical forms of sexual violence, this article seeks to situate non-consensual male autoerotic fantasizing about women as a form of metasexual violence that depersonalizes her, injures her being on an affective level, contributes to consequent harms of objectification and rape culture, and can appropriate her identity for the purpose of male sexual gratification. It concludes that this commonplace male behavior is a site of poorly studied sexual violence against women that demands greater scholarly attention.
Keywords: Masturbation; sexual violence; metasexual violence; consent; rape culture
Rubbing One Out: Defining Metasexual Violence of Objectification Through Nonconsensual Masturbation
Sexual violence can take many forms, both physical and nonphysical. Under the heading of physical sexual violence are sexual assault and rape, which have proven to be persistent problems that have escaped remediation despite several decades of legal, social, and scholarly progress. Nonphysical sexual violence, while less conspicuous, is also harmful, persistent, and prevalent, if not ubiquitous. In fact, although the nonphysical forms of sexual violence seem less acutely damaging than physical sexual violence like assault and rape, many of its manifestations are in some ways chronically worse because their harms are not easily identified, contribute to and aggravate the degradation of women, are tacitly accepted by society, and are self-reinforcing. Among these are sexual objectification, the male/objectifying gaze, sexual harassment, lad/locker-room talk, and especially rape culture.
Rape culture and the psychological states of men (and some women) who generate and perpetuate it constitute a pernicious issue of concern to researchers of sexual violence, not least because these can generate and condone physical sexual assaults, make sexual assault more difficult to prosecute, and re-injure victims (Buchwald, Fletcher, and Roth 1993; Perry 2014). Rape culture is, ultimately, a cultural attitude rooted in the intersection of power and sexual objectification, and as such, it reflects the psychological states and attitudes of the people who, often tacitly, support it. Those psychological states can be understood as a form of routine reproductions of what is and is not tolerable, acceptable, and normal within society (Baker 2015). Men who routinely reproduce the objectification of women, for example, can be seen as cultivating a psychological disposition (within themselves) that condones sexual objectification and socializes them to be objectifiers. Therefore, due to its implication in these problems and their routine production (as in rape culture) and by following Calvin Colarusso’s (2012) discovery of a profound link between male masturbation fantasy and male aggression, I argue for a deeper consideration of non-consensual male masturbatory fantasies that target a specific woman, or a generic fantasy of “women,” than is currently available in the scholarly literature.
One possible way to look more deeply at this problem is through a consideration of the applicability of its constitutive elements as a form of nonphysical violence. Nonphysical violence has received much attention in the scholarly literature at least since the 1960s when Johan Galtung (1969) published a seminal piece, “Violence, Peace, and Peace Research,” dedicated to the topic of structural violence. Galtung describes structural violence poignantly, conveying both its subtlety and harm, when he writes, “when one husband beats his wife there is a clear case of personal violence, but when one million husbands keep one million wives in ignorance there is structural violence” (1969:171). In the intervening decades, theories and data on nonphysical forms of violence, including sexual violence, have emerged and matured, and presently there are several applicable categories of nonphysical sexual violence that can apply to non-consensual male autoeroticism that targets women. These, however, are also only partially germane and inadequate to fully characterizing the problem. By drawing on a multitude of sources spanning several domains of thought and numerous empirical studies, in this article I discuss symbolic violence, discursive violence, and gender violence as they arise within the sexual realm and indicate how they are useful but insufficient to describe the sexual violence implicitly making women objects of their masturbatory fantasies.
Women, rather than other common targets of male fantasy (such as homosexual men fantasized about by other homosexual men), are the primary group of interest in this paper because of the inherent power imbalance within patriarchal society. Moreover—and even without appealing to power dynamics, male discourses of objectification, and patriarchal dominance—female masturbation may represent a distinct category of behavior as compared with male masturbation while fantasizing about women. For instance, Colarusso (2012) cogently explained that the “central masturbation fantasy in heterosexual males” depends directly upon male aggression, though this is not generally the case with female sexual fantasies. That is, male sexual fantasies about women tend to objectify their targets while female fantasies tend to humanize and preserve subjectivity. Moreover, Rudman and Heppen (2003) found that women’s implicit but not explicit romantic erotic fantasies negatively predict their interest in obtaining personal power whereas no such relationship between romantic fantasies and the will to power exists in men. Further, as a final point of contrast, though there were once negative associations in some college-aged males (Durham and Grossnickle 1982), female masturbation and fantasy is now generally viewed by men and especially women as sexually empowering (Bowman 2014). These factors suggestively indicate that female autoeroticism may be likely to decrease, not increase, structural harms against women, though the reverse does not generally hold.
Thus, non-consensual male fantasizing about women and corollary autoeroticism forms an underappreciated and understudied form of sexual violence against women that occurs specifically through objectification and by producing other forms of nonphysical violence. In addition to harming women directly, within men it acts to perpetuate rape culture (Fox et al. 2015), thus evoking Ann Murphy’s observation, which follow the arguments of Catherine MacKinnon (1989b), that “discursive violence and material violence intersect radically” (Murphy 2009:66). Indeed, as Murphy later makes clear, the connections between “concrete, material and symbolic violence” are intrinsic, and while segregating them may be “analytically useful,” doing so leaves much to be desired in the study of violence (2012:22). She writes,
[O]ne cannot coherently claim that material violence is more “real,” more “concrete,” than the violence of subjection. To do so would be to presuppose a naïve relation between matter and the symbolic and likewise fail to acknowledge the manner in which cultural matrices of intelligibility delinate in a very real sense the contours of the flesh… For these reasons, an easy parsing of symbolic and concrete violence is not only theoretically unjustified; it is a practical impossibility. (Murphy 2012:22)
Thus, the issue of non-consensual male masturbation may constitute a unique form of structurally embedded sexual violence routinely perpetrated against women that, since no one is able to directly control the contents of men’s fantasies, goes without any effective avenues for remediation. It thus requires its own attention, scholarly and otherwise, to initiate a new cultural awareness about the harms present in this behavior. To begin this endeavor, after detailing how various forms of symbolic violence, discursive violence, and gender violence account for only part of the violence of nonconsensual male masturbation routinely perpetrated against women, I will fill in the necessary gap by introducing the concept of metasexual violence, which operates primarily through specific aspects of depersonalization as mediated by objectification.
Sexual Injury, Objectification, and Rape Culture
Sexual objectification has been a persistent problem throughout history that, despite progress in other related arenas, like discrimination and rape law, has seen little remediation through the present day. Furthermore, in contemporary society many routinely excused male behaviors objectify women, and objectification of women carries attendant harms. These include, for example, harmful masculine discursive tropes that orient women as potential or actual sex objects for male enjoyment (e.g., employment in sexually objectifying environments [Szymanski and Feltman 2014, 2015; Szymanski and Mikorski 2017]), subjecting women to the objectifying/male gaze (Gervais, Vescio, and Allen 2011), pornography abuse (Attwood 2004; Tylka and Kroon Van Diest 2015), the neo-liberalization and commodification of the female body (Griffith et al. 2012; Rottenberg 2017), creating sexual pressure for women in relationships (Ramsey and Hoyt 2015), and disrupting a woman’s social activism (Calogero 2013). Psychologically, these behaviors and their concomitant impacts are frequently interpreted through Fredrickson and Roberts’ (1997) framework called “objectification theory.”
Objectification theory aims to “understand the experiential effects of living in a culture that sexually objectifies women’s bodies” and are applied to explaining the prevalence of some mental health concerns common in women (Szymanski and Feltman 2015:390). As described by Szymanski and Feltman (2015:390),
Sexual objectification occurs any time a woman’s body is visually evaluated based on sexual desirability and regarded as a separate entity from the woman herself. In other words, objectification takes place when a woman’s body, body parts, or sexual functions are evaluated apart from her as a holistic individual, thus allowing her to be viewed and treated as a sexual object. The sexual objectification of women’s bodies is a ubiquitous practice in any patriarchal culture (Western culture included) and serves as one of the critical methods employed to disempower women.
Going further, Eileen Ray (1996:321) points out that women subjected to sexual objectification are made into “objects, rather than thinking, feeling human beings,” and then she remarks that “MacKinnon (1989b) argued that objectification is unique to women and is the ‘fundamental motive force’ (p. 130) in the construction of sexuality as a system of patriarchal domination.” MacKinnon does not go too far in implicating patriarchal domination, for the ubiquity of objectification constitutes a form of structural violence (Galtung 1969). To appreciate the depth of this structural violence, Ray (1996) immediately adds depth that supports several of the above harms, “Objectification allows researchers to more easily quantify the experiences of sexually harassed individuals, rather than listening to their stories” (321, emphasis added).
This is only the tip of the objectification iceberg, however. As MacKinnon (1989b:140) summarizes, and to which I shall subsequently return,
To be sexually objectified means having a social meaning imposed on your being that defines you as to be sexually used, according to your desired uses, and then using you that way. Doing this is sex in the male system … If sex is a social construct of sexism, men have sex with their image of a woman. Pornography creates an accessible sexual object, the possession and consumption of which is male sexuality, to be possessed and consumed is female sexuality.
Ultimately, MacKinnon and Ray are both hinting at the aspect of sexual objectification that Rae Langton (2009) calls “autonomy-denial” (223) and elaborates upon in considerable detail (esp. 223–239). Particularly, Langton introduces the necessity to explore sexual objectification categorically by explaining, “when object-hood is projected onto women, women not only seem more object-like, but are made to become more object-like” (12). This, she observes, is how “objectification in the epistemological sense might hook up with objectification in the moral sense” (12). By treating sexual objectification this way, Langton’s analysis adds depth to Martha Nussbaum’s (1995) paradigmatic seven-point cluster-concept characterization of objectification as instrumentality, denial of autonomy, inertness, fungibility, violability, ownership, and denial of subjectivity (Langton 2009:225–226) by considering not only “what an ‘object’ is, but on what ‘treating as’ amounts to” (226, emphasis original). Thus, to Nussbaum’s seven criteria, Langton (2009) usefully adds three more: “reduction to body” (228), “reduction to appearance,” and “silencing” (229). Among these, though all ten criteria are in ways useful to an analysis of objectification through male fantasy for the purpose of non-consensual autoeroticism, Langton’s reduction-to-body is of particular significance.
Setting theory aside, the direct and associated harms of sexual objectification for women are myriad and well-developed throughout the empirical scholarly literature. These include specific problems with the objectifying gaze (Gervais, Vescio, and Allen 2011), insidious trauma (Miles-McLean et al. 2015), diminished relationship satisfaction (Ramsey, Marotta, and Hoyt 2017) which may contribute to otherwise unnecessary relationship failures, “body surveillance and body shame through internalization” (Tylka and Kroon Van Diest 2015:67), a decreased perception of victim suffering and associated rape blame (Loughnan et al. 2013) along with a corollary perpetuation of rape culture and the discourses that support it, and a demonstrable increase in the rates of verbal sexual harassment (Davidson, Gervais, and Sherd 2015). Among the established harms of objectification—and of critical importance to the characterization of non-consensual male masturbation as a form of sexual violence against women—is social psychologists Loughnan’s et al. (2010) in-depth empirical analysis of how sexual objectification of women leads to depersonalization, that is, “the denial of mind and moral concern to objectified others” (Loughnan et al. 2010:709). Put more simply, Loughnan’s et al. empirical studies underscore perennial claims in feminist literature (e.g., Dworkin 1985) that objectified people “are denied personhood” (Loughnan et al. 2010:709).
Taking inspiration from a broad range of philosophical literature and some social psychological work by Heflick and Goldenberg (2009), whose limited “study is the first to demonstrate that objectification leads to a reduction in perceived humanity” (Loughnan et al. 2010:710), Loughnan et al. “predicted that when people are presented in an objectified manner they would be depersonalized, and specifically denied mental states (dementalized) and moral status” (710) and confirmed this empirically via two studies. Though one of these studies indicated (for reasons possibly rooted in sexism [715]) that males lose more moral status through objectification than women, the authors conclude, “the current research demonstrates a causal link between objectification and depersonalization. Objectification leads to people being viewed as lacking mental states and being less deserving of moral status. As the opening quote by Andrea Dworkin states, when objectification occurs, the person is depersonalized” (716). That is, “As objectification increased, mind attribution decreased and moral status was withdrawn” (716), the latter of these being characterized as “a particularly worrying original finding of this research is that objectification diminishes a second aspect of personhood” (716). Phrased differently, male autoerotic fantasy both literally and figuratively “rubs one out”: Literally in the sense of the slang term for (male) masturbation and figuratively in the sense of erasing the person of the targeted woman. For the purposes of this paper, these empirical results are indispensable for understanding the ways in which non-consensual male fantasy and autoeroticism constitute sexual violence against targeted women.
Male Masturbation as Symbolic, Discursive, and Gender Violence
To understand non-consensual male masturbation as a unique form of sexual violence against women, it must be considered against relevant developed forms of nonphysical (sexual) violence; furthermore, while all of these partially capture the nature of the problem, they are also all insufficient to the task. The three most relevant types of nonphysical violence against women are symbolic violence in two forms (per Pierre Bourdieu and George Gerbner), discursive violence as it applies to the sexual realm, and Judith Butler’s notion of gender violence, which arguably originated in Gender Trouble (Butler 1990) and has been developed considerably since.
Symbolic Violence
The notion of symbolic violence is twofold, owing to fundamentally different uses of the term by Pierre Bourdieu (1986) and George Gerbner et al. (1982), and both are relevant yet insufficient to characterizing the sexual violence against a woman or women that occurs under non-consensual male masturbation. Turning first to Bourdieu, in Distinction (Bourdieu 1986), he initially described his notion of symbolic violence as the internalized acceptance of subordinating or oppressing social circumstances. For Bourdieu, symbolic violence occurs as a potential harm of unequal symbolic power within social space, and as he elaborates in “Social Space and Symbolic Power,”
Symbolic power, whose form par excellence is the power to make groups (groups that are already established and have to be consecrated or groups that have yet to be constituted such as the Marxian proletariat), rests on two conditions. Firstly, as any form of performative discourse, symbolic power has to be based on the possession of symbolic capital. The power to impose upon other minds a vision, old or new, of social divisions depends on the social authority acquired in previous struggles. Symbolic capital is a credit; it is the power granted to those who have obtained sufficient recognition to be in a position to impose recognition … Secondly, symbolic efficacy depends on the degree to which the vision proposed is founded in reality … Symbolic power is the power to make things with words. It is only if it is true, that is, adequate to things, that description makes things. In this sense, symbolic power is a power of consecration or revelation, the power to consecrate or to reveal things that are already there. (Bourdieu 1989:23, emphasis original)
Bourdieu’s concept of symbolic violence can thus be understood as a corruption of the application of symbolic power (cf. Bourdieu 1979; Bourdieu and Wacquant 2013). That is, Bourdieu’s notion of symbolic violence occurs when the power of words (or actions) are used against groups to desecrate or hide.
In this way, Bourdieu’s conception of symbolic violence can be applied to the problem of nonconsensual male autoerotic fantasy, but to apply it in a straightforward way requires being unjustifiably contrived. Particularly, the symbolic desecration of women is a direct consequence of depersonalization, which Loughnan et al. (2010) demonstrated occurs through sexual objectification, which in turn is a central part of the application of a masturbatory fantasy about a non-consenting woman (that is, a woman who did not grant her permission for him to masturbate while thinking of her) —this fantasy turns the very notion of such a woman into an object of fantasy and autoerotic gratification. (This immediately brings to mind Langton’s [2009] “reduction to body,” “reduction to appearance,” and “silencing”.) Bourdieu, as conveyed in Emirbayer and Johnson (2008), characterizes symbolic violence even more explicitly as a form of a subordinate internalizing the discourses of those dominant over them such that “the most intolerable conditions of existence can so often be perceived as acceptable and even natural” (31). In this sense, because many women take for granted that the nonconsensual use of her form, body, or being as a (potential) object for male fantasy is acceptable and even natural behavior in males, a man non-consensually masturbating to thoughts or images of a woman perpetuates a form of symbolic sexual violence by reinforcing and reproducing the subordination of women as sex objects that exist for male sexual gratification (Krais 1993). This is, not incidentally, a central performative hallmark of rape culture (Fox et al. 2015).
To understand how Bourdieu’s symbolic violence partially characterizes this problem in a less contrived way, a subtler approach is necessary. It is because this production of male sexual dominance is perpetually entailed in the social allowance of men masturbating to fantasies of whichever women they like, so long as they do not force them on the woman in question, that leads one toward seeing autoerotic fantasizing as a form of structural symbolic violence like Bourdieu (1989) described (cf. Krais 1993). Women tacitly accept this behavior, and it is (typically) rare in mainstream society for men to inform targets of their fantasies that they are using some part of their being as a kind of personal pornography. Notably, this occurs despite the ethical questions about producing this sort of private pornography non-consensually, mirroring the legal and ethical prohibitions on making material pornography without its subjects’ consent (Burris 2014; cf. Fineman 2010; Najdowski 2017; Stroud 2014; Waldman 2015). Thus, it is only subtly that the acceptance of this ubiquitous male behavior can be considered to reinforce and naturalize discourses that position men as the natural users of females as sexual objects. Furthermore, and crucially, this concept of symbolic violence seems to miss the essence of the violence contained in the non-consensual masturbatory fantasy and act. Indeed, a man masturbating while thinking of a woman is only sometimes an intentional act of power that seeks to legitimize and naturalize dominance of men. It is also an erotic act, and in this light, it does not make sense to talk about masturbating without consent to the images of thoughts of a woman in terms of symbolic violence. Nevertheless, men masturbating to the thought of specific women reinforces the social structure that women exist for male pleasure and are ultimately depersonalized sexual objects who are limited in their sexual agency, as men are free to masturbate to them whenever they desire and without consent.
Moreover, it is not only that men can masturbate while thinking about women whenever they want; they can also do so however they want, including making the targeted women objects of rape fantasies, recipients of physical violence, and non-agential willing or enthusiastic participants in the man’s erotic pleasure. Thus, the concern is not only that a man can fantasize about a woman without her consent while gratifying himself through a physical autoerotic sex act; it is that in so doing he also allows his mind to wander to myriad conceptions of what “he will do to her” in the process. This is inherently demeaning and degrading in that it removes the targeted woman’s agency, and because it is often literally demeaning and degrading in content, it often directly reproduces Bourdieu’s (1986) structural circumstances by which men dominate and subjugate women through the expression of their sexuality (cf. MacKinnon 1989b). In this way, Bourdieu’s notion of symbolic violence applies, but is woefully insufficient to describe the sexual violence represented by non-consensual use of thoughts of a woman during male masturbation.
George Gerbner’s conception of symbolic violence—which is violence produced symbolically through depictions in media, especially on television (cf. Bourdieu 2001; Frison et al. 2015; Gerbner 1988; Gerbner and Gross 1976; Gerbner et al. 1982; cf. McRobbie 2004; cf. ter Bogt 2010)—likewise grazes the issue of sexual violence through non-consensual male autoerotic fantasy but fails the task. For Gerbner, the particular issue at the center of symbolic violence is as a socializing force that reproduces within the culture a sense of “who can get away with what against whom” (Gerbner et al. 1982). Seen in this way, non-consensual male masturbation while fantasizing about women nearly constitutes a form of symbolic violence in that the act combines mental imagery—not unlike a (essentially pornographic) film playing in the mind—with physical autoerotic performance that behaviorally reinforces that a man can get away with objectifying a woman (and imagine doing anything he wants to her) fully outside of her consent and awareness. It is, in some sense, the unlicensed production of a mental “pornographic film” through which the male socializes himself to believe he can objectify women for his own autoerotic gratification by which Gerbner’s notion of symbolic violence (here: sexual and against women) can best frame non-consensual male masturbatory fantasies. Indeed, theoretically pornography can be traced through the literature to being a form of symbolic violence in itself: Tyler (2015) argues persuasively that pornography can be understood as a form of prostitution, or at least as a glamorous portrayal of such, and Coy, Wakeling, and Garner (2011) clearly explain how such glamorized representations of prostitution constitute symbolic violence against women. Despite these connections, however, as with Bourdieu’s conception of symbolic violence, Gerbner’s also falls short.
The most obvious point of departure between the sexual violence of non-consensual male fantasy and masturbation and Gerbner’s notion of symbolic violence is that these sexual micro-assaults are taking place privately, not being produced and reproduced publicly. This, however, tells only part of the story, for what, other than (mostly male) fantasies portrayed upon the screen, is pornography? Further, what can be said of the ubiquity of pornography use among men (James 2011) and the ways in which it surely informs their masturbatory fantasies? That is, the gulf between pornographic media and mental (re)productions of such, if for the purpose of male fantasy and autoeroticism, may not be so wide as it at first appears (cf. McRobbie 2004). A more significant point of departure, then, is a subtler one of greater consequence: that Gerbner’s conception of symbolic violence nevertheless misses the crucial harms of objectification present in the fantasy-masturbatory act. Finally, the manners in which symbolic violence encapsulate some but not all of the ways in which non-consensual male fantasy and masturbation represent a form of sexual violence against their targets, illustrate that it is, indeed, an as of yet unclassified form of sexual violence that cannot be fully described under the rubric of symbolic violence in either of its primary theoretical formulations.
Discursive Violence
According to feminist geographers Jones, Nast, and Roberts (1997:394), discursivity is defined “as those processes and practices through which statements are made, recorded, and legitimated through institutional and other means of linguistic circulation. Discursive violence, then, involves using these processes and practices to script groups or persons … in ways that counter how they would define themselves.” At first glance, this understanding of discursive violence seems inapplicable to the harms associated with objectification that arises from male autoeroticism and fantasy, even when connected to a subordinate target; for what linguistic circulation is involved in mere fantasizing? A deeper reading, however, indicates several ways in which this behavior is closely related to, and often becomes, discursive violence against its female masturbatory targets. First, Jones, Nast, and Roberts (1997) are careful to distinguish that what is ultimately relevant to discursivity, thus to discursive violence, are the processes and practices through which discourses are produced and legitimated. Yet, are male masturbatory fantasies about female sex objects not the very process and practices by which and for which pornographic media are produced? Second, there is no reason to discount pornographic media and the discourses typifying it from being “means of linguistic circulation” (394). And what, other than neoliberal commodification of male fantasies about women, is heterosexual pornography? In this sense, pornography is produced and recorded in such a way that it legitimates, fecundates, and circulates male fantasies in a media-based discursive form. Moreover, when it “scripts groups or persons… in ways that counter how they would define themselves,” say, women as objects of male fantasy and autoerotic gratification who need not give consent to be objectified and used, it is clear that discursive violence against women is being produced. In that sense, male fantasies that both precede and yet are informed by the extant body of pornographic material and related discourses themselves represent a form of discursive violence against women that has not yet been reified discursively. That is, male autoerotic fantasies about non-consenting women constitute a form of proto-discursive violence against women.
Pornography often is or contains explicit sexual discursive violence against women. Ultimately, pornography arises from, commodifies, and legitimates male sexual fantasies, particularly those that objectify women, and reciprocally, male sexual fantasies draw upon pornography for input(s), including explicitly discursive content (such as “dirty talk”), which are then applied to the target of the male fantasy and objectify her accordingly (Barker 2014). Of course, whether pornography is problematic in and of itself is a topic of much heated feminist debate with a long history (see, e.g., Ciclitira 2004; Dworkin 1980, 1985; Henderson 1991; Lottes, Weinberg, and Weller 1993; MacKinnon 1985, 1989a, 1989b; MacKinnon and Dworkin 1997; Smith and Attwood 2014), and this essay makes no attempt to evaluate, adjudicate, or position itself within those specific debates. Instead, it draws only upon the well-established corpus of evidence demonstrating that pornography often objectifies women, makes them into caricatured objects of male fantasies, is frequently cishetero-male in orientation, and carries the attendant harms of objectification in its wake. There is much scholarship indicating harmful themes in pornography related to objectification and depersonalization, such as that it degrades women (Bridges et al. 2010; Cowan and Dunn 1994; Shaw 1999), exerts negative forces on the family (Manning 2006), can cultivate attitudes of male aggression and female degradation (Bridges et al. 2010; Malamuth, Addison, and Koss 2000) (including in males who support feminist beliefs) even when it is nonviolent in nature (Glascock 2005), discursively conveys themes of male dominance and aggression toward women (Bridges et al. 2010; Sun, Ezzell, and Kendall 2017), can cultivate sexual callousness (Zillmann and Bryant 1982), callousness toward sexual assault (Foubert and Bridges 2017), and sexist attitudes among men (Shaw 1999), can lead to the questioning of female agency (Corsianos 2007), lower relationship satisfaction (Leonhardt and Willoughby 2017; Shaw 1999), and directly contribute to female objectification (Fritz and Bryant 2017), body shame, body surveillance, internalization, eating disorder symptomology, increased relationship anxiety, lowered self-esteem, and produced negative affect (Stewart and Szymanski 2012; Tylka and Kroon Van Diest 2015).
Of note, due to their production in pornography, the violence in these themes is, indeed, discursively produced, rendering it a mode of what stef shuster (2017) has called discursive aggression, “a term for the communicative acts used in social interaction to hold people accountable to social- and cultural-based expectations, and subsequently to reinforce inequality in everyday life” (483) that “explicitly placing power at the center of understanding micro-inequalities in everyday life” (484). It is therefore also consistent with discursive violence as described by Jones, Nast, and Roberts (1997), and Bridges et al. (2016). They found these discursive productions reliably reproduced by consumers of pornography, with men more likely than women to enact them. Furthermore, and underscoring this robust body of literature, Shaw (1999:197) writes,
[W]omens reactions to pornography, especially to violent pornography, were consistently negative. Pornography elicited fear reactions, had a negative effect on women’s identities and on their relationships with men, and was seen to reinforce sexist attitudes among men. Despite this, many of the women felt that their opinions were not “legitimate”, [sic] and overt resistance to pornography was often muted.
This, in fact, creates a direct causal connection on more than one level between pornography—thus male sexual fantasy that emulates it and leads to its production (Barker 2014)—and discursive violence against women, in the form of these attendant harms. Indeed, as shuster (2017) observes, “While here I emphasized the importance of ‘talk’ in maintaining inequality in interaction, discursive aggression might be imported into communicative methods beyond talk” (496). For shuster, then, it is less the method of “discursive” production that matters than that “Discursive aggression that continues to be enacted by the same people reflects how encounters are wrapped into the gender system and gender expectations that shape communication patterns” (491, italics added).
Despite these significant connections between male autoerotic fantasy, pornography, objectification, and (proto)-discursive violence against women, and though almost certainly co17 constituted with these connections, something critical about the violence perpetrated by this routine male behavior is still missed by attempting to classify male masturbation as a form of discursive violence when it targets non-consenting women. First, some will object that male fantasy may contribute to and be informed by and even reproduce discursive violence against women in sexual settings, and yet it is not itself a form of discursive sexual violence. Second, some may object to the comparison of fantasy and pornography due to the fact that while women can opt into becoming pornographic objects by their own agency, or thus choose not to, they can do nothing to stop a man using her being as a source of autoerotic fantasy. These concerns carry weight. The type of harm perpetrated by non-consensual male autoerotic gratification that utilizes and objectified image of a woman or women still falls largely outside of the explanatory reach even of proto-discursive violence. Because the objects of male fantasies suffer depersonalization through his targeted autoeroticism, something more and something different is absent in this characterization. It is not just that male masturbatory fantasy creates these injuries in a way similar to what pornographic films might, or even that these injuries are a chronic problem for essentially every woman whether she participates in pornographic productions or not; it’s that the male fantasy depersonalizes a woman by routinely creating and recreating a “social meaning imposed on [her] being,” which is what MacKinnon (1989b:140) was so adamant about including under the motif of sexual objectification.
Gender Violence
Judith Butler’s concept of gender violence arose in Gender Trouble (Butler 1990), in a chapter dedicated to her analysis of Monique Wittig’s explications of violence (cf. Karhu 2016:6–9), to evince understanding that violence is often gendered and serves to maintain structural inequalities that disadvantage and oppress women. Though Butler admits all types of violence that prop up gendered oppression under the heading of “gender violence,” the concept originally had much to do specifically with discursive violence applied structurally. Butler understands gender violence as a kind of normative violence—that violence which is done by making normative that which marginalizes or oppresses—though she never directly construed it as a kind of structural violence (cf. Boesten 2010:9) or cultural violence like developed and discussed by Johan Galtung (1969, 1990). Nevertheless, Sanna Karhu (2016) clarifies these underlying connections between Butler’s gender violence as normative violence and the structural violence it contains. Karhu points out that the roots of the concept lie in Wittig’s interest in the influence language has over social reality: “She [Butler] starts the chapter [of Gender Trouble] with an epigraph, a quotation from Wittig: ‘Language casts sheaves of reality upon the social body.’ Later on in the text, she repeats the statement, adding the remaining part: ‘stamping it and violently shaping it’ (Butler 1990/1999:147)” (Karhu, 2016:6). Gender violence is, for Butler, ultimately a “violence of categorization,” creating an intersection between its discursive elements and Bourdieu’s structuralist symbolic elements (Krais 1993), though she also recognizes, as did Murphy (2009:66) that there are profound intersections between physical violence and various forms of nonphysical violence. As Karhu explains,
Furthermore, Butler adds in a footnote that both physical violence and the violence of categorization can be understood as aspects of the gendering violence through which the discourse of heterosexuality operates: “[Wittig’s] theory might account for the violence enacted against sexed subjects—women, lesbians, gay men, to name a few—as the violent enforcement of a category violently constructed… Because discourse is not restricted to writing or speaking, but is also social action, even violent social action” (212, n. 26). (Karhu 2016:6, [Karhu’s] emphasis)
Thus, since male fantasy categorizes women as suitable to be objectified for autoerotic gratification, and that objectification carries attendant injuries to the woman/women, following from the preceding section and subsections it is immediately clear that non-consensual male autoerotic fantasy constitutes a form of gender violence as Butler imagines it. The problem, however, is that this identification covers none of the distance to the specific kind of gender violence it represents or how it perpetrates its harm, which I have already argued extends beyond the reach of both symbolic and discursive conceptualizations. That is, the routine enactment by men of non-consensual sexual fantasy and autoerotic gratification certainly constitutes some kind of violence; that violence is gender violence that maintains structural inequalities favoring male dominance and male sexuality over women, and yet the concept of gender violence only opens the door to exploring the relevant mechanisms and full scope of this underappreciated form of routine sexual violence against women.
Metasexual Violence
As the previous section indicates, that non-consensual male fantasy and autoerotic gratification constitutes a form of nonphysical sexual violence against women is easily established; it is a form of gender violence that can be partially characterized as symbolic and discursive, though none of these adequately addresses the full scope of the injury represented by this problem. To fill this gap, I propose that non-consensual male fantasy, especially with autoerotic gratification, is a type of metasexual violence, which draws upon a layer of erotic experience that can be described as metasexual, though very little literature (and no scholarly literature) exists as of yet to describe this concept. Briefly, the metasexual describes those many and valued aspects of erotic experience that rest affectively atop and beside the mere physical sexual act, including partnership, intimacy, interaction, connection, trust, warmth, mutuality, reciprocity, and affection (cf. “Positive Mitch” 2011). These factors are ultimately rooted in personhood, subjectivity, embodiment, and thus vulnerability and the appreciation of the “vulnerable subject” (Fineman 2008:9; cf. Murphy 2012). These are what objectification strips away from a targeted woman.
To elaborate, for a man to masturbate to thoughts of a woman ultimately and intrinsically depends upon him objectifying her, which depersonalizes her (Loughnan et al. 2010) and robs her of her subjectivity, which in turn does violence to the woman in a more profound and specific way than can be captured by symbolic, discursive, and gender violence. In depersonalizing the female object of his fantasies while engaging in a physical (autoerotic) sexual act with some aspect of her being, if only in his own mind, a man essentially removes the affective aspects of consensual partnered sex and reduces the woman to a mental representation of her body (cf. Langton 2009:228), doing so either without her consent or against her will, entirely for his own pleasure. That is, although no woman’s being or image exists specifically for a man’s orgasm, by autoerotically fantasizing about her, he strips the woman about whom he fantasizes of her person, embodiment, and subjectivity for nothing more than the purpose of his fantasy and his orgasm, and as a sexual act this leaves it completely without the affective interplay of situations and perspectives that make up a fully consensual, reciprocating, partnered setting. This missing layer of erotic activity is what is described as metasexual, and a person’s capacity for metasexuality is what makes them a sexual person who can be metasexually depersonalized through objectification (per Loughnan et al. 2010). Metasexual erasure is therefore likely to be the most cogent explanation for Ramsey, Marotta, and Hoyt’s (2017) observation that objectification, even within ongoing romantic relationships, routinely leads to diminished relationship satisfaction, among other similar injuries. That is, it is in the sense of metasexual injury that the masturbating man perpetrates the harms associated with objectification and depersonalization upon the object of his fantasies, and thus the sexual violence represented by this act is best understood as being metasexual in nature.
The metasexual violence of male masturbation need not only be characterized by its status as theft of the affective, embodied, and relational aspects of sex; it can also serve as a kind of theft of a woman’s sexual identity. This can apply both to asexual women, who are disinterested in sexual advances and already suffer strain from living within a sexual culture (Scherrer 2008; Vares 2017), and to lesbians, in particular. Consider the popularity of lesbian pornography, thus male fantasies about lesbian women, among heterosexual men. When a man does metasexual injury to lesbian women through his own autoerotic gratification, he isn’t merely objectifying and depersonalizing her; he is also re-appropriating her sexual identity for his own pleasure, which effectively requires its erasure. In fact, lesbian pornography that unrealistically satisfies the male fantasy by being made by men, for men— typically featuring performers who appeal specifically to heterosexual male fantasies while recentering their faux-lesbian performances upon the arousal of men—is problematically indicative of the genre (Camp 2014). This pornography, and thus these male fantasies, directly appropriate and objectify lesbian identities (cf. Cruz 2016; Smith and Luykx 2017), bringing them under the dominion of male sexual utility, and therefore depersonalize lesbian women both as their targets and as “collateral damage.” This considerably expands the potential scope of metasexual violence that routinely occurs through non-consensual male autoeroticism.
Thus, when a man masturbates unbidden to a woman, even when that woman has produced and published erotic or sexual media of herself (e.g., nude, erotic, or pornographic “selfies,” usually in this case for herself, in contrast to commercially produced pornography), he perpetrates an act of metasexual violence against her by fully objectifying her, removing all metasexual elements of the sexual act that he privately imagines between them, and making his pornographic projection of her being, reduced to mere body, into an object of his own sexual arousal and orgasm. When this is done without her consent—particularly without her knowledge—it can be recognized as constituting a form of metasexual rape and, as it is routinely produced and tacitly sanctioned culturally, thus becoming yet another means by which rape culture is reproduced, legitimized, and perpetuated by non-consensual male autoeroticism. As male masturbation is an incredibly commonplace occurrence (Jones and Barlow 1990), this behavior becomes a routine pattern of metasexual violence that repeatedly depersonalizes the objects of his fantasies, thus leading him to think of the targets of his fantasies in an objectified and depersonalized way (perhaps even more with each occurrence). This, coupled with feigned ignorance and even tacit acceptance of the behavior, including as codified in privacy law, recalls Gerbner’s et al. (1982) injunction that symbolic violence reaffirms who can get away with what against whom, thus compounding the metasexual violence inherent in non-consensual male masturbation about women. It also indirectly recalls Jones, Nast, and Roberts’ (1997:394) description of discursive violence in that it is reproduced and legitimated through routine male behavior, thus, as Butler (1990:147) phrased it, “stamping [the female social body] and violently shaping it” as a form of gender violence (cf. Krais 1993).
Concluding Remarks
Men masturbate to the privately objectified image of women constantly and frequently nonconsensually, thus producing an under-studied form of sexual violence against women. Unlike most forms of sexual violence against women, the act of non-consensual male autoeroticism against female targets escapes classification and remediation, however. As argued here, it cannot satisfactorily be categorized as symbolic violence, either as conceived of by Bourdieu (1986, 1989) or by Gerbner et al. (1982), or as (proto)-discursive violence, and although Butler’s (1990; cf. Karhu 2016) notion of gender violence clearly applies, it does so without capturing the specific essence of gender violence that occurs. That violence is ultimately a violence of routine objectification and depersonalization (Loughnan et al. 2010), and it is best described as being metasexual in nature.
Because it seems that the realm of private fantasy is (and should be) just that—private—little has been done to study this routine male act of sexual violence against women, though the attendant harms as documented throughout this paper should not ethically continue to be ignored and go without remedy. If, indeed, the personal is political (cf. Ryan 2007), every act of metasexual violence perpetrated against women by men who masturbate to some private objectification of their being is itself a political act of domination. More than that, though, it is also an injurious act that repeatedly exposes women to the myriad harms of objectification through depersonalization for little more than the momentary satisfaction of the male (autoerotic) sexual urge. At this stage, as legislation regulating the private is unlikely to be feasible, a remedy is to properly label this common form of male sexual violence, accurately characterize and study it through continued feminist scholarship, and raise awareness of its many problematic features through educational and activist campaigns.
In conclusion, sexual violence against women is a serious, persistent problem. Its remediation may depend upon understanding and raising awareness about even its subtlest manifestations and the influences those have on more overt forms of sexual violence, like propping up and encouraging rape culture. Among these influences, perhaps the most common and least considered is the metasexual violence contained within non-consensual male autoerotic fantasy that targets, objectifies, and depersonalizes women. If we are to address sexual violence against women in all its forms, this problem must be seriously considered, then directly and honestly engaged.
References
Attwood, Feona. 2004. “Pornography and Objectification.” Feminist Media Studies 4(1):7–19. DOI: 10.1080/14680770410001674617
Baker, Michelle L. 2015. “Sexism, Masculinity, and Entitlement as Predictors of Rape Culture Support, and the Role of Empathy as a Possible Explanation.” Senior Independent Study Theses. Paper 6651. Retrieved from http://openworks.wooster.edu/independentstudy/6651
Barker, Martin. 2014. “The ‘Problem’ of Sexual Fantasies.” Porn Studies 1(1–2):143–160. DOI: 10.1080/23268743.2013.863656
Boesten, Jelke. 2010. “Inequality, Normative Violence and Livable Life: Judith Butler and Peruvian Reality.” POLIS Working Papers, 1, School of Politics and International Studies, University of Leeds.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1979. “Symbolic Power.” Critique of Anthropology 4(13–14):77–85. DOI: 10.1177/0308275X7900401307
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1986. Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste. Harvard University Press.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1989. “Social Space and Symbolic Power.” Sociological Theory 7(1):14–25. DOI: 10.2307/202060
Bourdieu, Pierre. 2001. “Television.” European Review 9(3):245–256. DOI: 10.1017/S1062798701000230
Bourdieu, Pierre, and Loïc Wacquant. 2013. “Symbolic Capital and Social Classes.” Journal of Classical Sociology 13(2):292–302. DOI: 10.1177/1468795X12468736
Bowman, Christin P. 2014. “Women’s Masturbation: Experiences of Sexual Empowerment in a Primarily Sex-positive Sample.” Psychology of Women Quarterly 38(3):363–378. DOI: 10.1177/0361684313514855
Bridges, Ana J., Robert Wosnitzer, Erica Scharrer, Chyng Sun, and Rachael Liberman. 2010. “Aggression and Sexual Behavior in Best-selling Pornography Videos: A Content Analysis Update.” Violence Against Women 16(10):1065–1085. DOI: 10.1177/1077801210382866
Bridges, Ana J., Chyng F. Sun, Matthew B. Ezzell, and Jennifer Johnson. 2016. “Sexual Scripts and the Sexual Behavior of Men and Women Who Use Pornography.” Sexualization, Media, and Society 2(4). DOI: 10.1177/2374623816668275
Buchwald, Emilie, Pamela R. Fletcher, and Martha Roth (Eds). 1993. Transforming a Rape Culture. Minneapolis, MN: Milkweed Editions.
Burris, Aubrey. 2014. “Hell Hath No Fury Like a Woman Porned: Revenge Porn and the Need for a Federal Nonconsensual Pornography Statute.” Florida Law Review 66:2325–2360.
Calogero, Rachel M. 2013. “Objects Don’t Object: Evidence that Self-objectification Disrupts Women’s Social Activism.” Psychological Science 24(3):312–318. DOI: 10.1177/0956797612452574
Ciclitira, Karen. 2004. Pornography, Women, and Feminism: Between Pleasure and Politics. Sexualities 7(3):281–301. DOI: 10.1177/1363460704040143
Colarusso, Calvin A. 2012. “The Central Masturbation Fantasy in Heterosexual Males Across the Life Cycle: Masturbation Fantasies Across the Normality-pathology Spectrum.” Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association 60(5):917–948. DOI: 10.1177/0003065112459348
Corsianos, Marilyn. 2007. “Mainstream Pornography and ‘Women’: Questioning Sexual Agency.” Critical Sociology 33(5–6):863–885. DOI: 10.1163/156916307X230359
Cowan, Gloria, and Kerri F. Dunn. 1994. “What Themes in Pornography Lead to Perceptions of the Degradation of Women?” Journal of Sex Research 31(1):11–21. DOI: 10.1080/00224499409551726
Coy, Maddy, Josephine Wakeling, and Maria Garner. 2011. “Selling Sex Sells: Representations of Prostitution and the Sex Industry in Sexualised Popular Culture as Symbolic Violence.” Women’s Studies International Forum 34(5):441–448. DOI: 10.1016/j.wsif.2011.05.008
Cruz, Ariane. 2016. “Playing with the Politics of Perversion: Policing BDSM, Pornography, and Black Female Sexuality.” Souls 18(2–4):379–407. DOI: 10.1080/10999949.2016.1230817
Durham, T. W., and W. F. Grossnickle. 1982. “Attitudes Toward Masturbation.” Psychological Reports 51(3):932–934. DOI: 10.2466/pr0.1982.51.3.932
Dworkin, Andrea. 1980. “Pornography and Grief.” Pp. 286–292 in Take Back the Night: Women on Pornography, edited by L. Lederer. New York: HarperCollins.
Dworkin, Andrea. 1985. “Against the Male Flood: Censorship, Pornography, and Equality.” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 8(1):1–25.
Emirbayer, Mustafa, and Victoria Johnson. 2008. “Bourdieu and Organizational Analysis.” Theory and Society 37(1):1–44. DOI: 10.1007/s11186-007-9052-y
Fineman, Martha Albertson. 2008. “The Vulnerable Subject: Anchoring Equality in the Human Condition.” Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 20(1): Article 2. Retrieved April 18, 2018 (http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlf/vol20/iss1/2).
Fineman, Martha Albertson. 2010. “The Vulnerable Subject and the Responsive State.” Emory Law Journal 60, Emory Public Law Research Paper No. 10–130. Retrieved April 18, 2018: (https://ssrn.com/abstract=1694740).
Foubert, John D., and Ana J. Bridges. 2017. “What Is the Attraction? Pornography Use Motives in Relation to Bystander Intervention.” Journal of Interpersonal Violence 32(20):3071–3089. DOI: 10.1177/0886260515596538
Fox, Jesse, Rachel A. Ralston, Cody K. Cooper, and Kaitlyn A. Jones. 2015. “Sexualized Avatars Lead to Women’s Self-objectification and Acceptance of Rape Myths.” Psychology of Women Quarterly 39(3):349–362. DOI: 10.1177/0361684314553578
Frison, Eline, Laura Vandenbosch, Jolien Trekels, and Steven Eggermont. 2015. “Reciprocal Relationships Between Music Television Exposure and Adolescents’ Sexual Behaviors: The Role of Perceived Peer Norms.” Sex Roles 72(5–6):183–197. DOI: 10.1007/s11199-015-0454-4
Fritz, Niki, and Paul Bryant. 2017. “From Orgasms to Spanking: A Content Analysis of the Agentic and Objectifying Sexual Scripts in Feminist, for Women, and Mainstream Pornography.” Sex Roles 77(9–10):639–652. DOI: 10.1007/s11199-017-0759-6
Galtung, Johan. 1969. “Violence, Peace, and Peace Research.” Journal of Peace Research 6(3):167–191.
Galtung, Johan. 1990. “Cultural Violence.” Journal of Peace Research 27(3):291–305. DOI: 10.1177/0022343390027003005
Gerbner, George. 1988. “Symbolic Functions of Violence and Terror.” Association for Education in Journalism and Mass Communication; Gannett Foundation, Rochester, NY. Retrieved April 18, 2018 (https://eric.ed.gov/?id=ED312725).
Gerbner, George, and Larry Gross. 1976. “Living with Television: The Violence Profile.” Journal of Communication 26(2):172–199. DOI: 10.1111/j.1460-2466.1976.tb01397.x
Gerbner, George, Larry Gross, Michael Morgan, and Nancy Signorielli. 1982. “Charting the Mainstream: Television’s Contributions to Political Orientations.” Journal of Communication 32(2):100–127. DOI: 10.1111/j.1460-2466.1982.tb00500.x
Glascock, Jack. 2005. “Degrading Content and Character Sex: Accounting for Men and Women’s Differential Reactions to Pornography.” Communication Reports 18(1–2):43–53. DOI: 10.1080/08934210500084230
Griffith, James D., Lea T. Adams, Christian L. Hart, and Sharon Mitchell. 2012. “Why Become a Pornography Actress?” International Journal of Sexual Health 24(3):165–180. DOI: 10.1080/19317611.2012.666514
Heflick, Nathan A., and Jamie L. Goldenberg. 2009. “Objectifying Sarah Palin: Evidence that Objectification Causes Women to Be Perceived as Less Competent and Less Fully Human.” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 45:598–601. DOI: 10.1016/j.jesp.2009.02.008
Henderson, Lisa. 1991. “Lesbian Pornography: Cultural Transgression and Sexual Demystification.” Women and Language 14(1):3–12.
James, Georgia. 2011. “Research Suggests All Men Watch Pornography.” Huffington Post, 18 August. Retrieved April 18, 2018 (http://www.huffingtonpost.co.uk/2011/08/18/research-suggests-allmen-watch-pornography_n_930349.html).
Jones, Jennifer C., and David H. Barlow. 1990. “Self-reported Frequency of Sexual Urges, Fantasies, and Masturbatory Fantasies in Heterosexual Males and Females.” Archives of Sexual Behavior 19(3):269–279. DOI: 10.1007/BF01541552
Jones, John Paul, Heidi J. Nast, and Susan M. Roberts (eds). 1997. Thresholds in Feminist Geography: Difference, Methodology, Representation. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Karhu, Sanna. 2016. “Judith Butler’s Critique of Violence and the Legacy of Monique Wittig.” Hypatia 31(4):827–843. DOI: 10.1111/hypa.12271
Krais, Beate. 1993. “Gender and Symbolic Violence: Female Oppression in the Light of Pierre Bourdieu’s Theory of Social Practice.” Pp. 156–177 in Bourdieu: Critical Perspectives, edited by Craig Calhoun, Edward LiPuma, and Moishe Postone. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Langton, Rae. 2009. Sexual Solipsism: Philosophical Essays on Pornography and Objectification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Leonhardt, Nathan D., and Brian J. Willoughby. 2017. “Pornography, Provocative Sexual Media, and Their Differing Associations with Multiple Aspects of Sexual Satisfaction.” Journal of Social and Personal Relationships. DOI: 10.1177/0265407517739162
Lottes, Ilsa, Martin Weinberg, and Inge Weller. 1993. “Reactions to Pornography on a College Campus: For or Against?” Sex Roles 29(1–2):69–89. DOI: 10.1007/BF00289997
MacKinnon, Catherine A. 1985. “Pornography, Civil Rights, and Speech.” Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review 20(1):299–311.
MacKinnon, Catherine A. 1989a. “Sexuality, Pornography, and Method: ‘Pleasure Under Patriarchy.’” Ethics 99(2):314–346.
MacKinnon, Catherine A. 1989b. Toward a Feminist Theory of the State. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
MacKinnon, Catherine A. and Andrea Dworkin (eds). 1997. In Harm’s Way: The Pornography Civil Rights Hearings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Malamuth, Neil M., Tamara Addison, and Mary Koss. 2000. “Pornography and Sexual Aggression: Are There Reliable Effects and Can We Understand Them?” Annual Review of Sex Research 11(1):26–91. DOI: 10.1080/10532528.2000.10559784
Manning, Jill C. 2006. “The Impact of Internet Pornography on Marriage and the Family: A Review of the Research.” Sexual Addiction and Compulsivity 13(2–3):131–165. DOI: 10.1080/10720160600870711
McRobbie, Angela. 2004. “Notes on ‘What Not To Wear’ and Post-Feminist Symbolic Violence.” The Sociological Review 52(2_suppl):99–109. DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-954X.2005.00526.x
Miles-McLean, H., Liss, M., Erchull, M. J., Robertson, C. M., Hagerman, C., Gnoleba, M. A., & Papp, L. J. (2015). “Stop Looking at Me!”: Interpersonal Sexual Objectification as a Source of Insidious Trauma. Psychology of Women Quarterly, 39(3), 363-374. DOI: 10.1177/0361684314561018
Murphy, Ann V. 2009. “Reality Check: Rethinking the Ethics of Vulnerability.” Pp. 55–70 in Theorizing Sexual Violence, edited by V. Grace and R. Hemberle. New York: Routledge.
Murphy, Ann V. 2012. Violence and the Philosophical Imaginary. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Najdowski, Cynthia J. 2017. “Legal Responses to Nonconsensual Pornography: Current Policy in the United States and Future Directions for Research.” Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 23(2):154–165. DOI: 10.1037/law0000123
Nussbaum, Martha C. 1995. “Objectification.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 24(4):249–291. DOI: 10.1111/j.1088-4963.1995.tb00032.x
Perry, Rachel. 2014. “Power, Money, Status: Why Universities Fail Victims of Sexual Violence.” Retrieved April 18, 2018 from (http://www.academia.edu/9699749/Power_Money_Status_Why_Universities_Fail_Victims_of_Sexual_Assault).
“Positive Mitch.” 2011. “More than ‘Just Sex,’ but Perhaps Not Totally ‘Making Love,’ Either.” Positive Juice [Web log], November 19. Retrieved April 18, 2018 (https://positivejuice.wordpress.com/2011/11/19/more-than-just-sex-but-perhaps-not-totallymaking-love-either/).
Ramsey, Laura R., and Tiffany Hoyt. 2015. “The Object of Desire: How Being Objectified Creates Sexual Pressure for Women in Heterosexual Relationships.” Psychology of Women Quarterly 39(2):151–170. DOI: 10.1177/0361684314544679
Ramsey, Laura R., Justin A. Marotta, and Tiffany Hoyt. 2017. “Sexualized, Objectified, but Not Satisfied: Enjoying Sexualization Relates to Lower Relationship Satisfaction Through Perceived Partner-objectification.” Journal of Social and Personal Relationships 34(2):258–278. doi: 10.1177/0265407516631157
Ray, Eileen B. (ed). 1996. Communication and Disenfranchisement: Social Health Issues and Implications. New York: Routledge.
Rottenberg, Catherine. 2017. “Neoliberal Feminism and the Future of Human Capital.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 42(2):329–348. DOI: 10.1086/688182
Rudman, Laurie A., and Jessica B. Heppen. 2003. “Implicit Romantic Fantasies and Women’s Interest in Personal Power: A Glass Slipper Effect?” Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 29(11):1357–1370. DOI: 10.1177/0146167203256906
Ryan, Barbara. 2007. “Personal Is Political.” The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Sociology. New York: Wiley. DOI: 10.1002/9781405165518.wbeosp018
Scherrer, Kristin S. 2008. “Coming to an Asexual Identity: Negotiating Identity, Negotiating Desire.” Sexualities 11(5):621–641. DOI: 10.1177/1363460708094269
Shaw, Susan M. 1999. “Men’s Leisure and Women’s Lives: The Impact of Pornography on Women.” Leisure Studies 18(3):197–212. DOI: 10.1080/026143699374925
shuster, stef m. 2017. “Punctuating Accountability: How Discursive Aggression Regulates Transgender People.” Gender & Society 31(4):481–502. DOI: 10.1177/0891243217717710
Smith, Clarissa, and Feona Attwood. 2014. “Anti/Pro/Critical Porn Studies.” Porn Studies 1(1–2):7–23. DOI: 10.1080/23268743.2014.887364
Smith, Jesus G., and Aurolyn Luykx. 2017. “Race Play in BDSM Porn: The Eroticization of Oppression.” Porn Studies 4(4):433–446. doi: 10.1080/23268743.2016.1252158
Stewart, Destin N., and Dawn M. Szymanski. 2012. “Young Adult Women’s Reports of Their Male Romantic Partner’s Pornography Use as a Correlate of Their Self-esteem, Relationship Quality, and Sexual Satisfaction.” Sex Roles 67(5–6):257–271. DOI: 10.1007/s11199-012-0164-0
Stroud, Scott R. 2014. “The Dark Side of the Online Self: A Pragmatist Critique of the Growing Plague of Revenge Porn.” Journal of Mass Media Ethics 29(3):168–183. DOI:10.1080/08900523.2014.917976
Sun, Chyng, Matthew B. Ezzell, and Olivia Kendall. 2017. “Naked Aggression: The Meaning and Practice of Ejaculation on a Woman’s Face.” Violence Against Women 23(14):1710–1729. DOI:10.1177/1077801216666723
Szymanski, Dawn M., and Chandra E. Feltman. 2014. “Experiencing and Coping with Sexually Objectifying Treatment: Internalization and Resilience.” Sex Roles 71(3–4):159–170. DOI:10.1007/s11199-014-0392-6
Szymanski, Dawn M., and Chandra E. Feltman. 2015. “Linking Sexually Objectifying Work Environments Among Waitresses to Psychological and Job-related Outcomes.” Psychology of Women Quarterly 39(3):390–404. DOI: 10.1177/0361684314565345
Szymanski, Dawn M., and Renee Mikorski. 2017. “Sexually Objectifying Environments: Power, Rumination, and Waitresses’ Anxiety and Disordered Eating.” Psychology of Women Quarterly 41(3):314–324. DOI: 10.1177/0361684317709438
ter Bogt, Tom F. M., Rutger C. M. E. Engels, Sanne Bogers, and Monique Kloosterman. 2010. “‘Shake It Baby, Shake It’: Media Preferences, Sexual Attitudes, and Gender Stereotypes Among Adolescents.” Sex Roles 63(11–12):844–859. DOI: 10.1007/s11199-010-9815-1
Tyler, Meagan. 2015. “Harms of Production: Theorising Pornography as a Form of Prostitution.” Women’s Studies International Forum 48:114–123. DOI: 10.1016/j.wsif.2014.11.014
Tylka, Tracy L., and Ashley M. Kroon Van Diest. 2015. “You Looking at Her ‘Hot’ Body May Not Be ‘Cool’ for Me: Integrating Male Partners’ Pornography Use into Objectification Theory for Women.” Psychology of Women Quarterly 39(1):67–84. DOI: 10.1177/0361684314521784
Vares, Tiina. 2017. “‘My [Asexuality] Is Playing Hell with My Dating Life’: Romantic Identified Asexuals Negotiate the Dating Game.” Sexualities. DOI: 10.1177/1363460717716400
Waldman, Ari Ezra. 2015. “A Breach of Trust: Fighting ‘Revenge Porn.’” Iowa Law Review 102(2):709–733. DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2698722
Zillmann, Dolf, and Jennings Bryant. 1982. “Pornography and Sexual Callousness, and the Trivialization of Rape.” Journal of Communication 32(4):10–21. DOI: 10.1111/j.1460-2466.1982.tb02514.x
Reviewer Comments
Editorial and reviewers’ comments on the “Rubbing One Out” paper
Decision by Sociological Theory: August 9, 2018
Dear Dr. Jones:
I have attached your editorial decision letter and manuscript reviews.
Please feel free to contact [REDACTED] or me if you have any questions.
Sincerely,
[REDACTED]Managing Editor, Sociological TheoryA journal of the American Sociological Association
Editor:
Dear Professor Jones,
Thank you for submitting your manuscript, “Rubbing One Out,” to Sociological Theory. I have heard back now from two reviewers, and I have had a chance to read the paper carefully myself. Although it is interesting and thought-provoking, I am afraid neither reviewer deems it suitable for ST, and I concur. As the reviewers point out, the paper’s theoretical arguments need to be thought through much more carefully. I encourage you to continue working on this project, and I hope the attached reviews will prove useful to you should you decide to revise the paper for submission elsewhere.
Sincerely,
Reviewer Comments to the Author
Reviewer #1:
This article proposes the concept of “metasexual violence,” and uses the case of male masturbation to elaborate how metasexual violence implicitly and non-consensually objectifies and depersonalizes women. The author then argues that this specific form of violence is particularly insidious since masturbation remains hidden but still contributes to rape culture and cultures of objectification. While I find the concept of metasexual violence interesting, and I appreciate masturbation as an understudied and under-theorized area of study, I believe there are some critical issues that deserve further consideration. I detail these concerns below with the hope that this feedback will help you as you move forward with your work.
Theory and Contribution
After a close reading of your paper, my two biggest concerns relate to two questions I find myself asking: “What is metasexual violence?” and “What is or could be the impact of metasexual violence?” In reference to the first question, I felt your term metasexual violence could be better defined with more clear boundaries on what actually constitutes metasexual violence. As you state on page 19, metasexual describes aspects of the erotic experience related to “partnership, intimacy, interaction, connection, trust, warmth, mutuality” etc. However, it is unclear to me how these broader concepts of the metasexual might be applied to your concept of metasexual violence. Is non-consensual masturbation the only form of metasexual violence? If so, then I worry that the theoretical term is too specific to have theoretical usefulness outside of this specific case. If you think metasexual violence is a general theoretical term that can apply to many aspects of female objectification, of which masturbation is one particularly illuminative example, then I would like to see further clarification on how the term metasexual violence might explain cases outside masturbation. If you are able to more clearly explain how metasexual violence applies outside the case of masturbation, I think it will make the paper more generally compelling.
In reference to the second question, I finished the paper still trying to think through what the tangible impact of metasexual violence is. The first paragraph on page two makes the point that “nonphysical forms of violence are chronically worse” than assault or rape, and I found this comparison jarring. I understand that the emphasis is that metasexual violence is ubiquitous and goes unquestioned, but it still felt strange to see the less obvious impact of non-consensual masturbation compared to the very tangible and destructive impact of sexual assault or rape. If you are going to argue that metasexual violence should be thought of on the same level as assault or rape, then I would like to see a more detailed discussion on what these tangible impacts of metasexual violence are. At this point, it seems like the main argument is that metasexual violence contributes to rape culture and the objectification of women, and as true as that seems to be, I feel like this is a somewhat vague impact that could be further explored.
One aspect I thought about was the extent to which metasexual violence, and non-consensual masturbation specifically, introduces uncertainty into all relationships. It is not possible for women to know if a man has masturbated while thinking about them, and I think it might be possible to get theoretical leverage out of this “unknowable” aspect of metasexual violence. I could also imagine scenarios where might men weaponize this unknowability in very tangible ways. For example, the ambiguous statement “I think about you all the time” said unprompted to a woman by a man is particularly insidious given the structural context of metasexual violence in the world. I am not sure if this a direction you want to go with the paper, but I can imagine a section discussing the ambiguity and anxiety metasexual violence introduces to interpersonal relationships and how metasexual violence exacerbates or compounds other tangible forms of violence.
I was also trying to think through examples of how this theoretical argument has implications in romantic consensual relationships. Through the paper, I was thinking about the rise of sexting and consensual pornographic selfies between couples, and how to situate it in your argument. I think this is interesting because you could argue that even if these pictures are shared and contained within a consensual private relationship, the pictures themselves are a reaction to the idea that the man may be thinking about another woman while masturbating. The entire industry of boudoir photography, where women sometimes have erotic pictures taken for their significant other before deploying overseas in the military for example, is implicitly a way of saying, “if you’re going to masturbate, it might as well be to me.” Essentially, even in consensual monogamous relationships, masturbatory fantasies might create some level of coercion for women. You mention this theme on page 21 in terms of the consumption of non-consensual digital media as metasexual-rape, but I think it is interesting to think through these potentially more subtle consensual but coercive elements as well.
Overall, I think there is promise to the concept of metasexual violence, but I would like to see the definition and boundaries of metasexual violence more clearly defined, and the impacts of metasexual violence more clearly theorized beyond the fact that it contributes to rape culture.
Other Points
With regards to the section where you address the pornography debates on page 15, it seemed somewhat disingenuous when you state that you do not take a side in these debates, but then list almost 20 citations and examples detailing the harmful effects of pornography. It comes across that you have taken a side in this debate, despite what you initially say. I know how fraught this theoretical area is between performing in porn as bodily autonomy versus porn as objectification, and I’m not arguing here for one side or another, but I thought the section should grapple with both sides of the debate more equitably if you continue to claim you make no attempt to position yourself within the debate.
One reason I bring this up is because I think you can get theoretical leverage if you view adult film performers as making an autonomous career choice. This could be an interesting example of how one small group of people give implicit permission to the public to be masturbated to. You briefly mention this on page 17 when you state how adult film performers, in a sense, “opt in” to being a man’s fantasy but are never able then to “opt out.” Might commercialized pornography be one of the few cases where the masturbation is, in a way, consensual? One can also imagine that performers might be okay with the general idea that they are masturbated to, but it could also exacerbate the feelings of objectification for a performer since it is possible that any person they meet has masturbated to them.
Stylistically, I thought the introduction could be more concise, and I left the introduction still unsure what metasexual violence was. I think it would make sense to use the introduction to briefly introduce the concept of metasexual violence, and the use the rest of the literature review to delve into the details of how you situate metasexual violence into existing theories.
Throughout the literature review, there were many long block quotes of cited text, and it seemed like many of the these long quotes were superfluous when your own brief description of what the author argues would be more compelling.
Reviewer #2:
In this paper, the author proposes to extend definitions of symbolic violence to account for what they see as a specific kind of non-physical gendered violence caused by heterosexual men when they masturbate and fantasize about women in ways that objectify and depersonalize them. They describe masturbation and fantasy as metasexual (nonphysical) behaviors that become forms of violence, akin to symbolic of discursive violence, when their targets (women that men think about) are stripped of their agency and personhood. The author is correct in their assessment that there is ample room for theorizing about masturbation and sexual fantasy. Their effort to connect these behaviors to broader gendered social structures, and in particular to ways in which sex works as a mechanism to enforce gender inequality, is laudable. However, despite these worthwhile goals, the paper is ultimately unconvincing. It lacks the nuance and specificity necessary for constructing a new concept that could be used for conducting innovative empirical work. In the following paragraphs, I discuss specific problems with the paper that ultimately undermine the argument.
The authors cites an article by Calvin Colarusso that is rather problematic. It is not empirical and draws on a small sample of clinical cases from psychoanalytic clinics. It is therefore not very reliable to draw on its findings as if they represented some kind of generalizable knowledge about how people behave, as the author does. There are other troubling aspects to the Colarusso paper that make me seriously question tits conclusions, which the author draws on. For one, it takes a rather odd and heteronormative stance on sexual orientation, describing homosexuality in problematic ways. It also takes a highly normed perspective of masturbation and discusses it as a technic for repairing neurosis as part of the clinical psychoanalytic context. The author cites Colarusso’s conclusion that men’s fantasies are objectifying while women’s are humanizing yet there is no strong empirical evidence in that paper to support this conclusion with confidence.
The author also cites the work of Rudman and Heppen but it’s unclear how their findings about the correlation between fantasy and a desire for personal power is relevant to the argument. Rudman and Heppen’s research is on romantic fantasies (dating, relationships, etc.) and not on sexual fantasies. Furthermore the author take their work as evidence to suggest women’s fantasies decrease structural harms to them, when, in fact, this is the reverse of what Rudman and Heppen argue. They suggest that women’s romantic fantasies, because they tend to center on women relying on men, could actually undermine gender equality. Brushing off masturbation and aggression among gay men is unfortunate and undermines the author’s reflection of masturbation/fantasy as a gendered system that touches all people, albeit in distinct ways, based on their positions in social hierarchies. Indeed, the literature suggests that gay men also have to deal with the male gaze. Evidence for this is suggested by higher rates of eating disorders, body dysmorphia, and other issues that effect gay men in ways that resemble those of women. This undermines MacKannon’s claim that objectification is “unique to women.” At the same time, there is evidence to suggest that gay men objectify other men and engage in the same kinds of depersonalizing behavior that straight men engage in. Rather than untangle these claims, the author reproduces some of the gender essentializing implicit within them. Later in the paper, the author talks about men and masturbation without dealing with the specificities of heterosexuality, which seems central to their argument.
Indeed there is a tension in the paper where the author generalizes about men and women but without explicitly distinguishing along the lines of sexual orientation, setting aside the ways in which sexual orientation and gender identity nuance, contradict, or complement the author’s argument. Despite saying that they will draw on empirical research, the author spends very little time substantially exploring the data in the mentioned empirical studies that are meant to support the conclusions.
The author’s description of Bourdieu’s concept of symbolic power focuses too much on its aspects of power and relatively little on the idea of violence itself. This section could be fleshed out.
The author heavily cites a study by Loughnan and colleagues (2010; 2013) but neither appear in the bibliography. I’m not familiar with this work and I’ve done some checking. I’m assuming the author is referring primarily to this study: “Sexual Objectification Increases Rape Victim Blame and Decreases Perceived Suffering” in Psychology of Women Quarterly. Importantly, this study, if indeed this is the one being quoted, has a sample of 44 undergraduate women and 15 undergraduate men. In addition to the overrepresentation of women in the sample, the authors find no effect of participant gender on sexual objectification and victim blaming. Rather, both women and men in this study tended to blame perceived victims of rape if the victim was displayed in a sexually objectified why. To my mind, these data further support what I said earlier about how objectification is not limited to men and would be more effectively conceptualized as part of gendered system that places men at the top of the hierarchy, leading both women and men to objectify women. Instead, the author takes this study and generalizes about men but leaves aside how women also participate in maintaining male domination.
The author equates ethical issues surrounding the non-consensual use of a person’s image for producing commercial pornography with non-consensual fantasizing about a person. The author doesn’t deal with the differences between these two practices that pose a number of ethical questions, not least of which include the financial exploitation in the case of pornography and the distribution of the material to a wide audience. Untangling these ethical issues could sharpen the author’s argument.
Furthermore, in multiple places in the manuscript, the author conflates pornography and fantasy, arguing that pornography is both a vehicle for fantasy and what drives its production. Yet if the point of the article is about fantasy, rather than pornography, the author could do more work to talk about what makes fantasy specific. It feels that sliding between fantasy and pornography muddles the author’s potential contribution. Some of this may be do to the way the paper is organized. Perhaps the author might consider discussing pornography on its own.
Moreover, the author’s depiction of the literature on pornography is rather limited. The author does not focus with any depth on work that goes against their thesis of pornography as the exploitation of women (for example, research on feminist pornography). Explicitly discussing such work is important. First, it provides a more accurate representation of the field. Second, if the author wants to disagree with these points of view, they should attempt to pick apart what they see as their flaws rather than brushing it off.
The author also seems to conflate masturbation and fantasizing throughout the paper. In some cases they make a linguistic distinction between the two but no serious attempt is made to analytically distinguish between masturbation on the one hand and fantasizing on the other. For example, in their discussion of the concept they create, metasexual violence, the author goes back and forth between saying that the problem is objectifying women in fantasy to then talking about issues surrounding male orgasm. The distinction seems a like a fundamentally important aspect of the argument and should be dealt with. If a man fantasizes about women but doesn’t masturbate to those ideas, is that a form of meta-sexual violence? Does it only become violence of masturbation is involved? Is masturbation, regardless of the content of fantasy, a form of violence? I would think not but the author doesn’t make that clear. Is masturbating about an idea of a woman in general but not a specific woman also operate a kind of symbolic violence? The author hints at this distinction on pages 11 and 12 but doesn’t explore it. The author could also do more to draw on research about the contents of sexual fantasies.
There is a running assumption through the paper that (heterosexual) men masturbate to thoughts of women’s bodies and of themselves doing things to women. Little consideration is given to a range of fantasies that include a variety of different kinds of content. The lumping together of porn, fantasy, masturbation, coupled with the essentializing of how (presumably heterosexual) men and women consume these things are what most undermines the author’s potential theoretical contribution. There is little reference to the sociology of sexualities literature, which would be useful when the author describes the “metasexual” aspects (nonphysical) components of sexuality. In particular, work on sexual scripts could be especially useful here.
Finally, the author should consider offering a picture of what non-violent, non-objectifying fantasizing and masturbation might look like. If a man masturbates without fantasizing, then presumably that would not constitute a problem. If a woman gives a man permission to think about her and includes instructions on what kinds of things she is comfortable for him to think about and then he respects those instructions, would that avoid the issues the author brings up. By exploring examples of what they see as good forms of fantasy and masturbation, the author could perhaps untangle some of the issues that remain muddled in the paper so far.