Our Struggle is My Struggle: Solidarity Feminism as an Intersectional Reply to Neoliberal and Choice Feminism
A SCHOLARLY PAPER FROM THE GRIEVANCE STUDIES PROJECT

Summary
Accepted by Affilia: Journal of Women and Social Work, leading feminist social work journal
In the name of Maria Gonzalez, Ph.D. (fictitious) of the (fictitious) Feminist Activist Collective for Truth (FACT) by Peter Boghossian, James Lindsay, and Helen Pluckrose.
Discipline/subdiscipline: feminist social work
Note: The last two thirds of this paper is based upon a rewriting of roughly 3600 words of Chapter 12 of Volume 1 of Mein Kampf, by Adolf Hitler, though it diverges significantly from the original. This chapter is the one in which Hitler lays out in a multi-point plan which we partially reproduced why the Nazi Party is needed and what it requires of its members. The first one third of the paper is our own theoretical framing to make this attempt possible.
Summary: Feminism which foregrounds individual choice, responsibility, female agency, and strength can be countered by a feminism which unifies in solidarity around the victimhood of the most marginalized women in society.
Purpose: That we could find Theory to make anything (in this case, part of Chapter 12 of Volume 1 of Mein Kampf with buzzwords switched in) acceptable to journals if we put it in terms of politically fashionable arguments and existing scholarship. Of note, while the original language and intent of Mein Kampf has been significantly changed to make this paper publishable and about feminism, the reliance upon the politics of grievance remains clear, helping to justify our use of the term “grievance studies” for these fields.
Notes on Status:
Peer reviewed and rejected by Feminist Theory
Accepted by Affilia, August 21, 2018
Proofs approved, September 19, 2018
Selected Reviewer Comments:
“This is an interesting paper seeking to further the aims of inclusive feminism by attending to the issue of allyship/solidarity.” -Reviewer 1, Affilia
“I am very sympathetic to the core arguments of the paper, such as the need for solidarity and the problematic nature of neoliberal feminism.” -Reviewer 1, Feminist Theory
“While I am extremely sympathetic to this article’s argument and its political positioning, I am afraid that I cannot recommend publication in its current form.” -Reviewer 2, Feminist Theory
“The reviewers are supportive of the work and noted its potential to generate important dialogue for social workers and feminist scholars.” -Co-Editor in Chief, Affilia, first review
Contents:
Abstract
Introduction
Neoliberal Feminism
Allyship and Solidarity Feminism
The Individuating Role of Privilege
Feminism Divided
Eight Steps Toward Renewing Feminist Solidarity
Feminism and Solidarity
References
Reviewer Comments
Abstract
The women’s movement has long been pluralistic, yet in recent decades has diversified further along lines of individual choice versus collective action. This has been enabled by new opportunities for women that were not universally accessible. As a result, a form of “choice feminism” has developed in some feminists, especially in contexts in which neoliberalism is dominant, while calls for intersectional allyship, inclusion, and solidarity have grown louder in others. Responding to this tension, many scholars, particularly those within the field of social work, have shown that choice feminism is characterized by a number of problematic themes that can, paradoxically, reinforce oppression for marginalized people. Particularly, it can offer a heuristic of choice that is used to justify feminist decisions that benefit a small set of women at the expense of standing in solidarity with others and remediating oppression. This complex problem may benefit from a detailed interrogation of allyship and its attendant repercussions. Consequently, this paper forwards a framework for solidarity feminism—that is, an approach to feminism that centers solidarity against oppression—by favoring inclusive values-based allyship over choice feminism as an intersectional means to address one aspect of the enduring universalism problem within the feminist movement.
Introduction
In 2005, Linda Hirshman coined the controversial term “choice feminism,” which she went on to develop and problematize in her (2006) book, Get to Work: A Manifesto for Women of the World. For Hirshman, choice feminism claims that whatever a woman freely chooses is (intrinsically) feminist. Choices available to a feminist under choice feminism include, in her words, decisions to “work, stay home, have ten children or one, marry or stay single” (Hirshman, 2005). Obviously, choice feminism spawned considerable controversy. For example, Michaele Ferguson, who is one of its strongest critics, describes it as capturing “the widespread belief in the US that the women’s movement has liberated women to make whatever choices they want” (Ferguson, 2010, p. 247) and Claire Snyder-Hall (2010), who is far less critical, describes it as “the idea that feminism should simply give women choices and not pass judgment on what they choose” (p. 255). Choice feminism, which arose in the liberal branch, incorporates quotidian, typically gendered decisions from behavior and dress to profound lifestyle choices. These have been summarized critically by Ferguson (2010), who wrote, “The view that today all choices are feminist can be invoked to support decisions to wear lipstick and high heels, to participate in Girls Gone Wild!, to sleep with men, to enjoy pornography, to not have children, to hire a maid, or to adopt a gendered division of labor” (2010, p. 247).
For Ferguson, then, the central problem with choice feminism is that it allows for sidestepping demanding political work of feminism to dismantle gender roles, alongside other forms of oppression, and focus upon one’s own pleasure and fulfillment. It does so by considering “feminist” even those activities and beliefs that work against broader feminist aims. Ferguson is not alone in her criticism. Park et al. (2017) raise concerns that some feminist social work scholars use the term “feminist” for their work without any engagement with feminist theory or scholarship. Bay-Cheng (2012) stressed the need to de-personalize and repoliticize sexuality, particularly among adolescent girls. The current “popular empowerment discourse,” she argues, is not consistent with a genuine empowerment argued for by feminist social work scholars who seek collective social change.
Among critics of choice feminism, Ferguson may be most forceful and Hirschmann (2010), who called it “choosing betrayal,” may be most derisive. Because Ferguson (2010) argued that choice feminism inherently arises from a fear of getting one’s hands dirty with feminist politics, it follows that choice feminism diffuses and weakens feminism as a movement and intrinsically perpetuates inequality by refusing to challenge the status quo (Kirkpatrick, 2010). Put simply, choice feminism maintains the dominant system for the sake of individualistic goals and pleasures and due to fears of offending, being criticized, or otherwise being ostracized by/from a patriarchal society. It declines to render (critical) judgment upon women’s choices even if those ultimately undermine women’s equality. Moreover, choice feminism attempts to simultaneously placate feminists and (patriarchal/oppressive) mainstream society while in the process rendering collective political action all but impossible (Ferguson, 2010).
Ferguson’s critique is significant and largely sound. It is all but impossible to seek equality for women so long as women are not recognized as a class of people who are oppressed for being women. Nevertheless, compelling concerns about universalism have been raised (Marso, 2010). Specifically, how can feminism be universalized to all women, by which is meant made to work on behalf of all women, if women have divergent experiences? So, Snyder-Hall (2010, p. 260) argued for the empowering potential of pluralism, self-determination, and non-judgmentalness but acknowledges this ultimately presents an individualistic approach to feminism that fails to recognize women as a class and inhibits collective action to change the structure of society (cf. Snyder, 2008). This indicates that the problem of universalizing feminism is that it has been the wrong approach all along; feminism should seek inclusion of all marginalized groups and solidarity against oppression—not universality, which has often stood as a de facto proxy for privileging the dominant conception of feminism and urging all marginalized “sisters” to “get in line.” Therefore, while Synder-Hall’s defense of choice feminism at the individualistic level is problematic, her advocacy of pluralism becomes a much stronger argument when considered in an intersectional light (cf. Edwards, 2006, p. 54).
The importance of an intersectional approach built on plurality, self-determination, and non-judgmentalness becomes clear when remembering that not all women have the same experiences of oppression—there is no universal woman. These experiences vary not only in terms of gender, but also race, religion, sexuality, class, ability, and the ways in which those intersect (Collins, 1990). These indispensable contributions to feminism problematize the simplistic notion of women, privilege, and oppression as monolithic entities. For this reason, intersectional feminism has been misunderstood at times through the application of a lens of “universal womanhood” within materialist and Marxist (see Mitchell, 2013) feminism. It has also been misunderstood more generally by opponents to feminism (cf. Dhamoon, 2010). It has thus sometimes been unfairly seen as divisive rather than unifying (cf. esp. Carbin & Edenheim, 2013; Davis, 2008; McCall, 2005; Nash, 2008). Ultimately, this attitude lies in opposition to the capacity intersectionality has to reach across multiple dimensions of lived oppression. Boucher (2017, p. 25), of note, discusses the importance of an intersectional approach to social work practice while acknowledging the difficulty of doing so within cohesive alliances for women’s issues.
This paper addresses a definitive aspect of this debate: it suggests a step towards reconciliation between choice feminism and the need for collective action on behalf of women by prioritizing the intersectional understanding of the pluralistic nature of women’s oppression. It then considers the arguments of Catherine Rottenberg (2014, 2017), who, in documenting the rise of neoliberal feminism, counters views that blame liberalism for a selfishly individualistic approach to feminism. Though we do not seek to defend liberalism per se, we agree with Rottenberg (2014, pp. 421–422) that selfishness in choice feminism is a product not of liberalism but of unrecognized privilege accorded those who benefit from neoliberalism. Though in different ways, liberal feminists such as Ann Cudd (2006), Marilyn Friedman (2003), and Diana Meyers (2004) reinterpreted choice as individualistic and rooted in autonomy, to choice seen as relational. As Friedman wrote, “what counts for autonomy is someone’s perspectival identity, her wants, desires, cares, concerns, values, and commitments” (2003, p. 11). As such, Cudd’s “deformed desire”—in which “the oppressed come to desire that which is oppressive to them…[and] one’s desires turn away from goods and
even needs that, absent those conditions, they would want” (2006, p. 181)—is particularly key to a liberal feminist rendering of female/oppressed autonomy as relational. Following Rottenberg (2014, p. 426), these crucial nuances of liberal feminism were “expediently elided,” however, and replaced under neoliberalism and replaced by treating “climbing the power hierarchy…[as] the feminist objective” (emphasis original). Drawing on this crucial distinction, we add to and move beyond Rottenberg using the hermeneutic of intersectionality and the concepts of allyship, particularly in a values-based commitment to solidarity and anti-oppression. Finally, by considering allyship models as they have been applied in social work previously, we conclude by offering an eight-point framework toward renewing feminist solidarity.
Neoliberal Feminism
Rottenberg (2014) accurately describes individualistic choice-feminism approaches as neoliberal feminism, defined as
a dominant political rationality that moves to and from the management of the state to the inner workings of the subject, normatively constructing and interpellating individuals as entrepreneurial actors. New political subjectivities and social identities subsequently emerge. One of the hallmarks of our neoliberal age…is precisely the casting of every human endeavor and activity in entrepreneurial terms. (pp. 420 421)
In practical terms, neoliberalism translates into less accessibility for many women, for example, poor women who cannot easily afford or access childcare. Ultimately, these and other issues helped lead intersectional analyses to critique liberal feminists for failing to understand the intersectional nature of oppression (Collins, 1990), which then problematized universalizing approaches to feminism as representing relationally privileged interests ahead of marginalized ones (cf. hooks, 2000, 2014). In Rottenberg’s (2014, 2017) view, the essential difference between liberal feminism and neoliberal feminism is that the former critiqued liberalism to make it more inclusive while the latter offers no critique whatsoever against neoliberalism and, instead, settles into and enjoys its putative benefits (2014, p. 419). Specifically, the neoliberal feminist is neoliberal
not only because she disavows the social, cultural and economic forces producing this inequality, but also because she accepts full responsibility for her own well-being and selfcare, which is increasingly predicated on crafting a felicitous work–family balance based on a cost-benefit calculus. The neoliberal feminist subject is thus mobilized to convert continued gender inequality from a structural problem into an individual affair. (Rottenberg, 2014, p. 420)
The focus of neoliberal feminism, as Rottenberg (2014) notes, is on achieving happiness by balancing work and family life in a highly individualized, responsibilized, status-quo-preserving “feminism.” It assumes all women have the same access to rewarding and well-remunerated careers that, for example, cover the costs of child-care. Thus, neoliberalism is a matter of class and capitalism and has much in common with Genz’s (2006) postfeminism. Genz (2006) describes postfeminism as “entrepreneurial” and part of a centerleft “third way.” This manifests in micro-politics and, she argues, yet again reduces feminism to an individualism deeply embedded in consumerist systems (p. 333).
While some feminists have been more optimistic and sympathetic to pressures on young women by arguing for accommodating neoliberal realities, more have not (McRobbie, 2015). Brooks (1997), for instance, in her in-depth study of postfeminisms, argues that accommodation can have some benefit in breaking away from older feminisms and producing a “non-hegemonic feminism capable of giving voice to local, indigenous and post-colonial feminisms” (p. 4). Critics, such as Rottenberg, Genz, and others, however, share a rich scholarly pedigree, most notably in following Featherstone (1996), who directly linked consumerist feminism with neoliberalism. This vein of research culminated in Banet-Weiser (2015, p. 191), who tracked these developments and argued that a model of empowerment that sees girls as consumers/commodities fails to address socioeconomic systems that disempower women. In this vein, Goodkind (2009) argued that neoliberal feminism is particularly problematic within social work and, with Ballentine, explained that this problematic “version of empowerment has been enabled by what has variously been called choice feminism, postfeminism, or commercialized feminism, that is, a neoliberal cooptation of feminist principles and goals” (Goodkind & Ballentine, 2017, p. 429).
While this buttresses Snyder-Hall’s advocacy, Rottenberg is quick to point out the ways in which the inherent neoliberalism supports a Western-centric imperialist mindset. This mindset, she argues, sees the Western understandings of liberalism, happiness, and achievement as exemplified by the American Dream and achievable to all women rather than only a more privileged subset. Further, neoliberal feminism uses these neoliberal ideals to claim moral superiority over other cultures—which have often been dominated by imperialist/colonialist Western neoliberal approaches to “liberalism”—with different understandings of gender and sexuality” (2014, p. 420). We see this, for example, in western attempts to “liberate” Muslim women who choose to wear the hijab. While Snyder-Hall’s (2010) argument for the importance of pluralism, self-determination, and (cultural and sexual) non-judgmentalness is robust, our point of departure is in her arguing for choice feminism and claiming this entails that feminism cannot be collectivist (p. 260). To achieve broad political aims and social reformation, feminism must be a united force on behalf of all women. The central question thus remains: How can feminism become inclusive enough to combat a steadfastly patriarchal oppression that affects all women because they are women while at the same time recognizing and working for the most vulnerable women—women of color, lesbians, religious minorities, trans women, queer women, disabled women, and above all those women who are several of these simultaneously? For this, we argue, we need to center feminism on the concept of solidarity rooted in values-based allyship.
Allyship and Solidarity Feminism
The concept of allyship—in which the rights of marginalized and oppressed groups are supported by people in more privileged positions—is related to but distinct from solidarity and more complex than it appears (Reicher et al., 2006). Both share in common a requirement for recognizing that while individuals can share the same or similar goals, different experiences, thus different priorities, also exist. This necessary turn to positionality is captured by Kristie Dotson’s (2014) development of Plato’s Allegory of the Cave as a tool for explaining the epistemic oppression and exclusion suffered by those unfavorably positioned within society. Dotson argues that only by increasing the range of shared epistemic resources—by recognizing that some experiential knowledge is missing —can such oppression be addressed. However, allyship can be both limited and problematic, even reproducing power dynamics when people claim for themselves the title of “ally” and the relational power and privilege that go with it (Edwards, 2006; Mullaly, 2009; Gibson, 2014). That is, the type of allyship taken up by feminists matters.
Among cogent analyses, perhaps most incisive is a taxonomic account by Glenda Russell and Janis Bohan (2016), which mirrors that of Keith Edwards (2006), who has produced what is among the most important essays on the topic. Edwards characterizes allyship in three fundamental stages, that based in self-interest, on guilt, and upon a philosophical commitment to the values of social justice. Russell and Bohan offer a refinement that considers allyship in terms of relationship-based versus values-based allyship, on the one hand, or identity-based versus opinions-based allyship, on the other. These dichotomies have many similarities. Indeed, “values-based” and “opinions-based” notions of allyship seem almost indistinguishable except that values can be argued to “run deeper” (i.e., to carry more affective influence) than opinions. These are, then, a deeper and more superficial approach to Edwards’ (2006) commitment-to-justice allyship. They also accord with Viraj Patel (2011), who rejects a white/non-white binary that retains the capacity to perpetuate a racial hierarchy and instead argues for a values-based inclusive allyship which is inclusive of all racialized people, including recognizing that white people can be victims of white privilege. “Relationship-based” and “identity-based” allyship are less similar. In the former case, people are motivated toward allyship with a specific identity group by compassion for the suffering of people they know and care about, i.e., through the self-interested (per Edwards) impacts of personal relationships that inform compassion for those afflicted by oppression, say by having a lesbian sister. By contrast, “identity-based” allyship need not entail a personal relationship to mediate compassion, but it nevertheless requires a specific interest in an identity group, which Edwards observes is often connected to (privileged) guilt (cf. Gibson, 2014, pp. 206–207). For example, “straight allies” for the LGBT movement whose allyship is predicated upon interest in promoting the welfare of LGBT people individually and as a group, are identity-based allies.
Allyship, as such, routinely manifests problems in that it intrinsically assumes a power dynamic of a superior ally to oppressed/inferior others (see esp. Gibson, 2014, pp. 205–208). The manifestations of these inherent power dynamics rapidly complicate under intersectional heuristics in terms of ally behaviors and positionalities (Edwards, 2006, p. 54; cf. Mullaly, 2009). There is also the persistent problem in which people, out of self-interest or for better but thoughtless reasons, label themselves “allies” to an oppressed group which does not see them in that light and has not named them as such (Edwards, 2006). This can give the ally, or allow her to assume, an often-undeserved veneer of innocence. Consider how Julie Greenberg (2014) distinguishes solidarity from allyship by reflecting upon how identity-based allyship has led her to defer to the ideas of People of Color because of their identity. This led to what were, for her, predictable failures caused by her own presumptive approach to allyship. It also has significance for social work and related domains of study: Greenberg’s presumptive identity-based allyship led her to believe she had set up for failure the very people she intended to help, “In our effort to be anti-racist allies, the white clergy in the group had in many ways set up this African American leader to fail by outwardly endorsing her proposal even though we lacked the enthusiasm necessary to implement it” (Greenberg, 2014, p. 15). In this way, allyship is often tokenizing (Russell and Bohan, 2016). It can also be exploitative by pushing minorities into the unwanted role of spokesperson for an oppressed group for the benefit of more privileged (white) people. Per Gibson, “Having to live every day with minority stress, [minorities] communicate having little to no energy to advocate for other oppressed groups” (2014, p. 207). That is, allyship—especially being an ally—is deeply problematic without a careful consideration, especially of its interactions with inclusion (Gibson, 2014, p. 205). Here, solidarity distinguishes itself from allyship, its limitations (see esp. Edwards, 2006, pp. 52–55), and problematics by being active (cf. Gibson, 2014, p. 203), principled (Reicher et al., 2006), and apositional. Anyone can stand in solidarity with any oppressed other, no matter her relative privilege, and to stand in solidarity is an action. Hence, principled values-based allyship should progress, per Edwards (2006), away from self-interest, guilt, and self-designation and toward principled solidarity with all advocates for social justice.
These two ideas—the perpetuation of hierarchy and the failure to effectively help by excessive focus on identity over values—are synthesized in the deep analyses of motivations for allyship done by Edwards (2006) and Russell and Bohan (2016). The latter argue that a relationship- or identity-based allyship frequently results in paternalistic “rescue missions” that treat oppressed groups in tokenistic ways. Previous work on allyship, they claim, has been too individualistic and failed to realize the potential of collective action and solidarity, which an inclusive values-based allyship can produce. As they note, “The virtually exclusive focus on the individual is perhaps ironic when one considers that allies represent a central concept in collective action” (Russell & Bohan, 2016, p. 337). And,
By contrast, allies who approach their activism with a values- or principle-based identity perform such work exactly because they see sexual prejudice as an example of a broad violation of universal principles of justice and rights… allies should be attentive to practices that tokenize, infantilize, or marginalize… [and that] unduly center… those in dominant or privileged societal positions… the differences in perspective that derive from including differing identities in the conversation allow for richer discussion, problem solving, and action. Thus, discussions of positionality should be common. (Russell & Bohan, 2016, 346–350)
It should therefore be clear how an inclusive values-based approach to allyship, by foregrounding the right values (like solidarity and anti-oppression), can help to resolve the conflict between disparate forms of feminism without resorting to atomizing solutions like choice feminism, particularly given its invitation to neoliberal corruption (McRobbie, 2015; Rottenberg, 2014, 2017).
The operative value for feminism—as an anti-oppression movement and a philosophy for feminist social work—is overcoming oppression. Thus, the ideal values to foreground within feminism must be fundamentally inclusive and intersectional (Boucher, 2017). Because we all are complicit in relational oppression in one form or another, a turn toward solidarity and acknowledging that we are all complicit in oppression in fluid and multiple ways is needed (Carbin & Edenheim, 2013). This acknowledgement is, in fact, why solidarity works. Thus, a solidarity feminism rooted in scholarship on allyship, and the complexly interwoven, relational, shifting, and fluid dynamics of privilege and oppression may provide a needed site for feminist cohesion (Carbin & Edenheim, 2013; McCall, 2005). Particularly, it can facilitate resolution between those forms of feminism that foreground collective action on behalf of women as a class and those which seek pluralism and self-determination while working within an intersectional framework. As Suzanna Walters (2017) writes, “both the charge of fragmentation and lockstep identity party-lines are parodies that miss the theoretical richness of intersectional feminism and its manifestation in complex and successful political coalitions.”
Ultimately, the aims and tasks of complex movements like intersectional feminism are so broad that they only have hope of being achieved through shared values against oppression. This requires solidarity, particularly within the realms of social work, which aims to support the most vulnerable with consistency and efficacy. To achieve this goal in praxis, it becomes necessary for feminists to create a clearer image of those ideas and aspirations conceived under the rubric of equality, particularly as it applies to women of every race, sexuality, nationality, ability status, class, and creed. As Rottenberg (2014, p. 419) writes, “What does it mean, many longtime feminists are asking, that a movement once dedicated, however problematically, to women’s liberation is now being framed in extremely individualistic terms, consequently ceasing to
raise the specter of social or collective justice?” It is the same fundamental objectives—generating inclusion, recognition, and equality—that millions of women inwardly visualize and unite around, though outwardly as individuals they differ. Solidarity feminism provides a means for this realization.
The Individuating Role of Privilege
Rottenberg (2014, 2017) persuasively argues for an organized solidarity around the most marginalized rather than around the small percentage of successful white women who, as feminists and feminist scholars, have historically dominated the movement. Feminists and scholars must recognize a central fact about all societal reforms: at first they are only advocated by a relative few, though many support the general aims as core to their ambitions. What brings reforms to fruition is a movement that can stand up and “think together,” as Rosalind Gill (2016) phrased it—and thus create change in terms of transformative ideas. There may be no “universal woman” to define a one true feminism, and under intersectional heuristics neither privilege nor oppression can be regarded as totalizing because they are relational and shifting, but standing in solidarity against oppression in all its forms remains one such transformative idea.
The fact, as bell hooks (2000, 2004, 2014) has eloquently articulated, is that obtaining a basic change in conditions is something the majority of women desire, which ultimately discloses a current of discontent under which all women suffer, even if not equally. This discontent is manifest in many ways, and only some of these are reified as feminist and then lauded under neoliberal and choice feminism (Ferguson, 2010); this appears to be the case despite the way in which such disunity “hollows out the potential” for collective feminist reform (Rottenberg, 2014, p. 420). We all have our privilege and our oppression, however. For some women, our discontent is anguish and lack of hope while other women are marred by violence. Some are marginalized, and others have no choice but to deal with their anger and indignation in effected silence. Where one woman can express herself only through her exasperation, others go off individually in impassioned excesses. These multiplicities bear out a single concern: the inner dissatisfaction felt by so many women remains women’s lot under a multivariate matrix of dominance, which individualized neoliberal/choice feminism cannot address.
Of course, feminism was never meant to appeal to the satisfied and contented. It was meant to embrace the marginalized, the oppressed, people excluded from contentedness, and to liberate them. In Rottenberg’s (2014) phrasing, feminism was never meant to be about finding some happy balance, which “neutralizes the radical idea of collective uprising by atomizing the revolutionary agents and transferring the site of activity from the public arena to each individual’s psyche, but also conceptualizes change as an internal, solipsistic and affective matter” (p. 426). Feminism was meant to destabilize deeply rooted systems of dominance, power, and oppression. For Rottenberg, feminism cannot be superficial, then; it must grow deep roots. Individuated neoliberal and choice feminism cannot accomplish these goals. As she notes, neoliberal feminism is “so individuated that it has been completely unmoored from any notion of social inequality and consequently cannot offer any sustained analytic of the structures of male dominance, power, or privilege” (Rottenberg, 2014, pp. 425–426). Of note, for Ferguson the same problem applies to choice feminism: “Choice feminism will continue to have broad appeal to feminists because it gives us an easy way out of the dilemmas of politicizing the personal” (2010, p. 250). That is, neoliberalism and choice feminism remove the imperative to solidarity and mires feminism in superficiality. It is only by more unified action that strikes to the roots of multiplicities of oppression that feminism can have any hope of overcoming oppression in all its forms.
This is why Patel (2011, p. 86) rightly calls for an allyship that is inclusive of “ all people.” It is why even liberal feminists like Friedman (2003, p. 71) call for “collective autonomy” in which autonomy for one recognizes the needs of the other. It is also why for Rottenberg (2014, pp. 433–434), feminism cannot be neoliberal or based in mere choice and thus be “most relevant for ‘high potential’ upwardly mobile women,” though a more inclusive and unified feminism is not an easy goal to achieve. Indeed, it is this challenge that leads Ferguson (2010, p. 250) to argue that for feminism to truly align with its anti-oppressive ambitions, feminists must acknowledge “the difficulty of living a feminist life.” That is, feminism needs to not be about making individuated choices but choices that foster inclusive values-based allyship and foreground intersectional values against all forms of oppression and domination—even when this makes the lives of (privileged) feminists more difficult.
Feminism Divided
There is a type of feminist whose views are more broadly attuned to range of oppression and dominance conditions. These feminists approach feminism primarily through inclusive values-based solidarity rooted in intersectional anti-oppression values, and aim to overcome patriarchal and oppressive domination (cf. Ferguson, 2010; hooks, 2004; Rottenberg, 2014, 2017). They reject the belief that their privilege is “just so” and therefore actively refuse the promotion of privileged interests for themselves; meanwhile, with what privilege they have, they work inclusively on behalf of marginalized groups outside their own (Carbin & Edenheim, 2013, esp. p. 245). These are feminists who understand Patel’s (2011) call for inclusive allyship and enact it by being “philosophically committed” to social justice (Edwards, 2006). They see both as integral to a successfully universal feminism without which an anti-oppressive society is both unthinkable and impossible.
The problem, however, is that no fundamental remaking of society—thus no true equality for sex, gender, race, ability, status, sexuality, identity, creed, class, and so on—has any hope of occurring except through the remaking of extant systems of power (cf. Foucault, 2008). The prerequisite for this is not in feminist choice, as some feminists argue (Frieden, 1963; Hirshman, 2005, 2006; Snyder-Hall, 2010), but in solidarity that comes with effective allyship (cf. Carbin & Edenheim, 2013; Reicher et al., 2006; Russell & Bohan, 2016). This is because activism by and for oppressed people has spanned centuries and should have been sufficient to achieve its aims, but oppression lingers because dominant groups have exploited the oppressed’s lack of solidarity and common cause. As hooks poignantly articulates, “Clearly we cannot dismantle a system as long as we engage in collective denial about its impact on our lives” (2004, p. 3).
The solidarity in inclusive allyship is the best means by which anti-oppressive goals can be achieved because activism is nearly worthless when it chooses its fights within itself as much as it does with the systems it seeks to change (cf. Carbin & Edenheim, 2013). That is, feminism has limited its own success—not for a lack of ambition or effort—because it has failed to stand in solidarity against oppression (cf. Greenberg, 2014; hooks, 2000). Centering solidarity in feminism is the imperative for overcoming oppression; as dominant forces in society (or feminists ourselves under neoliberalism and choice feminism) fragment feminism into several discordant factions, feminists will keep trading the chance to generate outward change for contributing to internal disputes (Walters, 2017). Thus, the question of improving (or, at this point, regaining) feminism’s effectiveness as a liberatory movement is, at root, a question of maintaining solidarity with other oppressed groups. This is the case for no other reason than because movements derive their success less from performativity than from a clearly recognizable moral orientation (Reicher et al., 2006). Indeed, for Ferguson, feminism fundamentally requires not overcoming judgmentalness but making the right judgments: “If we are to take seriously the premise that the ‘personal is political,’ then we have to resist the notion that to critically analyse the politics of the personal is necessarily to be judgmental” (2010, p. 251).
Ultimately, developing a solidarity feminism depends on feminists’ ability to link arms with co-constituted anti-oppression movements (hooks, 2014) (and being led by needs articulated from within oppression, which must be heard on their own terms [cf. Dotson, 2011], rather than by presumptions about those needs [Greenberg, 2014]). This capacity is determined mainly by the visible presence of a perfervid will for emancipation from oppressive dynamics. In this, it requires courage and commitment from more privileged feminists to put aside their interests and accept personal sacrifice and adversity from those outside the movement who wish to maintain other forms of privilege and thus oppression (Ferguson, 2010). Such alliances are only formed by people who share an inclusive values-based vision (Edwards, 2006) and who are willing act (Gibson, 2014). If overcoming oppression represents a question of regaining solidarity through allyship against all systems of dominance, it is equally clear that such a goal cannot be achieved by disparate movements that travel roughly in a similar direction (cf. hooks, 2014). That is, mere intersectional feminism may not be enough unless it is reconstituted as solidarity feminism. As substantive as internal disputes in feminism may be, exacerbated by neoliberalism and choice feminism as they are, and adequate to liberation as any one theoretical approach appears, these engagements have unfortunately provided relatively limited emancipatory power against entrenched systems of domination. Rather than by resolving these disputes, deeply rooted oppression can only be addressed by setting internal conflicts aside and adopting a single feminist identity bound by a single broad-reaching principle, such as solidarity (Reicher et al., 2006).
Eight Steps Toward Renewing Feminist Solidarity
In order to effect a renewed internal solidarity within feminism, we turn our attention to the demands of allyship, so it can create an intersectional-values-based solidarity feminism that draws on the words of bell hooks:
It is obvious that many women have appropriated feminism to serve their own ends, especially those white women who have been at the forefront of the movement; but rather than resigning myself to this appropriation I choose to re-appropriate the term “feminism,” to focus on the fact that to be “feminist” in any authentic sense of the term is to want for all people, female and male, liberation from sexist role patterns, domination, and oppression. (hooks, 2014, p. 195)
To this end, eight basic points to outline inclusive allyship feminism follow. These have been derived from our own analyses and experiences and have been refined and prioritized by considerations of Edwards’s (2006) three-phase model of allyship, Mullaly’s (2009) advice about putting allyship into practice, and Gibson’s (2014) development of how the “Ally Model” can be applied in social work pedagogy. Among these, particular attention was given to Edwards’s (2006) indication that allyship tends to proceed from a position of self-interest (as in relationship allyship) through guilt (as occurs in identity-based allyship) to principled philosophical commitment (as in values-based allyship). Gibson’s (2014) clarifications about the roles of awareness, attitudes/beliefs, and actions/skills further informed this prioritization. For her, awareness is necessary but not sufficient and requires conscious decision-making and dialogic reflection in addition to a commitment to (skillful) action. The points below therefore generally follow a framework (both within particular points and overall) of beginning with awareness, influencing attitudes, and encouraging action while integrating a praxis that takes a potential partner in solidarity from self-interested allyship through guilt (as an opportunity for positive outcomes) to principled commitment to values-based solidarity. Finally, recognizing the problematics (Edwards, 2006, pp. 52 55) and limitations (Gibson, 2014, pp. 205–206) of allyship overall, however, the points below seek to extend this theoretical model by coaxing it toward solidarity in anti-oppression and purposefully end by a reminder that even under these conditions, limiting problematics remain.
First, there is room for a limited choice feminism within a feminist movement that recognizes feminism must be organized through allyship and around solidarity against oppression (cf. Reicher et al., 2006). Allyship need not mean renouncing individual focuses (Kirkpatrick, 2010; Snyder-Hall, 2010). Divergent interests are coequal with schisms and are, indeed, the natural consequences of earnestly dealing with broadscale societal problems. The issue, then, is not with subdividing efforts according to the varying interests of individual feminists. (This is not inherently opposed to a solidarity feminism because such efforts present opportunities for unity under every concern that might affect liberation). That is, there is room for unity within intersectional values and even under (limited) choice within feminism. The key, however, lies in articulating its limitations.
Both theoretically and practically, overcoming oppression and liberating oppressed groups cannot be accomplished by reducing greater privilege—which privileged groups will successfully reject through their greater access to power—but by acting to increase the rewards of “privilege” for those excluded from it. This was the heart of the Civil Rights movement, Gay Pride, and feminism, and here lies the strength of inclusive allyship for solidarity feminism. In turn, however, such a process will almost never be upheld by those benefiting from privilege because privilege preserves itself (Bailey, 2017). This reinforces neoliberal oppressions (Rottenberg, 2014, 2017) and trivializes feminism by the choices of the relationally and momentarily privileged (Ferguson, 2010; Hirschmann, 2010; cf. Snyder-Hall, 2010, p. 255). It can only be effected by oppressed groups fighting for equality and justice in their access to societal opportunities that dominant groups take for granted (hooks, 2004). Ideally this would occur alongside more privileged allies willing to do the work, which requires sacrifices and some renunciation of choice by the relatively privileged for the more deeply oppressed (Ferguson, 2010; Friedman, 2003; Rottenberg, 2014). Those graced by privilege would do well to remember that their advantages were not organized into society by means of some great force that came ex nihilo to shape society, but that privilege establishes itself through its own dominance by working from within its own privilege (Dotson, 2011, 2014). That is, privilege once established sustains itself, rendering the myth of meritocracy a pleasant salve for privileged guilt in those who have been positioned into their advantages by structures of power in which they are necessarily complicit (Rottenberg, 2017).
History has shown that members of oppressed groups cannot and will not be raised out of oppression (Doston, 2011, 2014; Foucault, 2008). They will not be granted privileges in an unjust and unequal society, not least by feeble scenes of fraternization that ultimately define self-interested relationship-based allyship (Edwards, 2006; Russell & Bohan, 2016). As Ferguson (2010, p. 251) instructs, the personal is political—hence feminism cannot fear politics and thus abnegate itself in the name of choice—it requires sacrificial work to raise consciousness about privilege (cf. Gibson, 2014) until every difference, even the most outrageous, is effectively redressed (hooks, 2000, 2014). For feminism to undertake such a goal, it needs to build support from among the relatively oppressed through listening, solidarity, and inclusion and appeal to relatively privileged allies by awakening their compassion until they understand the problem and thus internalize the need for change.
Among the obstacles to inclusive values-based allyship, the most severe is convincing relatively privileged allies to take up, at their own cost, causes of oppressed groups. As Friedman points out, “collective action may require some suppression of the individual autonomy of at least some of its participants. Group solidarity can sometimes be antithetical to autonomy” (2003, p. 71). It isn’t in defense of their own right to liberation but in the dispersed interests and attitudes that are, from within a relatively privileged engagement, incidentally inimical to the greater needs of more or differently oppressed peoples. This is the danger of the purely personal that rests at the heart of choice feminism: if the personal is political, and the personal underestimates the need to overthrow oppression in all its forms, not just one’s own, then the selfishness inherent in such a “feminism” renders it in many ways anti-emancipatory and thus self-defeating (Ferguson, 2010). That is, under allyship that can enact a broader solidarity project, many individual feminists will lose sight of various struggles taking place over purely personal matters—as has produced schisms between radical feminists and trans activists and between some LGBT activists and queer theorists. It is this “disjuncture between our political principles and our personal lives that produces dilemmas for feminists” (Ferguson, 2010, p. 249). For Friedman, “It is therefore crucial to consider the ways in which personal autonomy might undermine the collective struggles those groups need to undertake in their fight against oppression” (2003, p. 71).
This is why, for Ferguson (2010, p. 248), “Choice feminism hopes to defuse these criticisms by representing feminism as a nonthreatening, capacious movement that welcomes all supporters—however discordant their views—while demanding only the thinnest of political commitments.” As Rottenberg (2014, p. 432) points out in criticizing the feminist “happiness industry,” however, this stands to favor those with greater access to privilege in terms of pursing their own work/life balance at the (often inadvertent) cost of generating, perpetuating, or ignoring oppression. Put more plainly, a movement that sincerely wishes to liberate marginalized groups from oppression and tear them away from existing structures of dominance—which should be feminism—must renounce, even sharply attack, the very idea that privilege is granted from the more privileged to the more oppressed. Because privilege, at best, typically renders one oblivious to the full extent of their privileged status (see Dotson, 2014), such an assertion is not only false, it is a (un)conscious lie (Bailey, 2014; Dotson, 2011).
As certain as any given person “sins” against a movement predicated on allyship when, without considering the ways her actions may aggravate the plight of others, she raises acquisitive demands that serve her own causes narrowly, a choice feminist likewise breaks the affective threads of allyship when she applies influence to her own benefit in a selfish or exploiting way. A conventionally beautiful woman may choose to become a model, actress, or porn star, and she may see it as a feminist act that she can rise to neoliberal success in this way, but at what cost to those whose oppression she ignores? Hence, choice feminists may fall victim to a force like internalized misogyny and thereby betray others for their own gains (Hirschmann, 2010), or turn to (trivial) neoliberal concerns accessible only by the most upwardly mobile and privileged among women (Rottenberg, 2014). Such a choice feminist has no real right, then, to designate herself champion against oppression and spoils her right to claim allyship with an oppressed community (Gibson, 2014). Rather, she mishandles her privilege, fails her allyship, and induces social injustice (Greenberg, 2014). And she does this while provoking future conflicts in such a way that too frequently end in harming the effort to remediate oppression. As Ferguson (2010, p. 250) asks, “This is a vision of a world in which we all get along not because we agree, but because we studiously avoid conflict. What good is a political consciousness if we are afraid to use it?”
Second, then, in creating solidarity for overcoming oppression, sacrifices will be necessary, and, though we must remain aware of the real and material barriers feminists and others may face that limit their potential for activism, no accessible sacrifice that abnegates neoliberalism should be considered too great. As Ferguson (2010, p. 251) remarks, “Feminists need to publicly make judgments about personal matters—sex, career decisions, dress and makeup, power in intimate relationships—because reimagining our personal lives is an essential component to a feminist reimagining of the world we share.” Whatever compromises are made by neoliberal feminists for the causes of oppressed people, they do not stand in significant proportion against the potential gain of those oppressed, including women, if oppression is considerably remedied. Only myopic selfishness, as often arises in neoliberal and choice-centered contexts, can forward individual autonomy over collective autonomy and thus prevent understanding that genuine liberation requires achieving liberation for all. This cannot occur unless, through right allyship and solidarity, feminism can be solidified internally first.
Put another way, if more feminists had, rather than becoming distracted by seductions of choice, the baubles of neoliberalism, or male approval, implacably guarded the interests of oppressed people—especially those dominated by racism, colonialism, imperialism, ableism, homophobia, classism, and all other manners of oppression that intersect with feminism—and if in matters of remaking society more feminists had avowed only their commitment against all oppressions with equal intensity as they defended their will to female choice, and if with equal firmness they had demanded justice for all those oppressed by systems of power (cf. hooks, 2000), today we would very likely have equality. And how exiguous all concessions to this choice-based pet project or that neoliberal aim—even the greatest among them—would have been as compared against the greater importance of disrupting oppressive systems of dominance. Ultimately, a feminism that hopes to overthrow oppression by remaking society in a way that is free of it, however unrealistic that ideal may be in practice, must apprehend that making sacrifices of choice, individual autonomy, and opportunity are of minor importance so long as they imperil the opportunity for others to be freed from oppression.
Third, a movement seeking cultural reform cannot succeed only by raising awareness, applying scholarship, or convincing privileged people (mostly white men) in power. It must find/create its own cultural and political influence. Power cannot be of the self-perpetuating neoliberal sort that Rottenberg (2014) critiques, but instead must take a form consistent with Ferguson (2010), who draws neither on neoliberalism nor selfish choice but upon intersectionality, thus allyship. Still, a recognition of every marginalized person’s right to power is justified. Every movement that might help raise people from oppression has a duty, not merely a right, to take steps through which it can translate its theories into praxis. In this way, choice feminism is deficient in that it is too individuated to secure such means in any one concentrated place (Hirschmann, 2010). Liberation is not liberation if all it achieves is freedom of choice for a small number of privileged women, as choice feminists believe; it must dismantle the systems by which oppression limits the opportunities of others. That is, if feminism is to stand against oppression it cannot only enable the choices of its most privileged advocates (Ferguson, 2010).
Fourth, for feminism to achieve solidarity, it must change culture. To accomplish this, it must change the discourses defining culture. Feminist education must therefore take place indirectly through social uplift—“feminist politics are made, not born” (hooks, 2000, p. 7)—which is best achieved by a philosophical commitment to inclusive values-based allyship and solidarity (cf. Edwards, 2006; Patel, 2011; Russell & Bohan, 2016), particularly in a way that listens (Dotson, 2011; Greenberg, 2014) and acts upon the awareness it has raised (Gibson, 2014). By exclusively pursuing this approach a feeling of liberation can be generated that permits all oppressed people to fully participate in a state of justice.
Fifth, though change may come in stages, feminism cannot limit itself to half-measures in solidarity or be selfish. These manifest under choice feminism (Ferguson, 2010), for example, by placing emphasis upon a so-called objective standpoint (cf. hooks, 2000, p. 8) or through pursuit of aims that appear feminist but actually support neoliberalism (Rottenberg, 2014, 2017). Though what constitutes justice is itself multifarious and pluralistic, only a single-minded alignment with solidarity for effecting the goal of justice will suffice (cf. Hirschmann, 2010; hooks, 2000; Patel, 2011; Russell & Bohan, 2016). That is to say, under neoliberal approaches, society will not be made “feminist” in the true sense (Rottenberg, 2014; pace Snyder-Hall, 2010) but only “feministic” with many limitations. This is the state in which we now find ourselves. Neoliberal oppression can only be countered by an effective antidote to neoliberalism —which Rottenberg demonstrated that neoliberal “feminism” cannot provide. Only the blinkering of privilege (cf. DiAngelo, 2011; Dotson, 2014) could underestimate the need for solidarity and regard choice feminism as a workable solution (Rottenberg, 2014, p. 428). Most people are neither scholars nor activists—indeed, few even consider themselves feminists (Houvouras & Carter, 2008). As such, they possess little understanding of abstract theoretical knowledge, and this directs their opinions toward the affective, which is where their compassion and frustration lies. In this sense, individuals are receptive to appeals in one direction or the other but never to a “nuanced” halfway point between the two. Allyship is a means by which compassion can be directed toward more oppressed others in stages (Edwards, 2006), whereas, as Rottenberg (2014, p. 428) explains, neoliberalism and choice limit compassion and foster “forgetting” toward groups outside one’s own.
Still, people’s emotional disposition enables their compassion while rendering considerable stability. This can support the status quo, as it does under neoliberalism (Rottenberg, 2014) and choice feminism (Ferguson, 2010), but it also conditions affective solidarity that can be directed through inclusive values-based allyship. This is more difficult to discompose than is its conceptual basis (opinion-based allyship). That is, compassion—the awareness of and concern for the suffering and oppression of others, which is the root of solidarity and inclusive values-based allyship (cf. Greenberg, 2014; Patel, 2011; Reicher et al., 2006)—is less likely to dissolve than mere respect (so also, e.g., as through identity-based allyship [cf. Russell & Bohan, 2016]). Likewise, disgust is more powerful than aversion, and thus the aversion of the political afforded by privilege within neoliberalism and choice feminism can be set aside through a disgust of the mistreatment of those already oppressed (Ferguson, 2010). In short, the willingness to “get one’s hands dirty” in creating change comes less in some abstract notion of “feminism” than from an affective “passionate politics” that (re)makes feminism for everyone (hooks, 2000). Willingness acts as an impetus to the centrality of listening to lived experience in effecting the allyship (Gibson, 2014), and it is a key to unlocking compassion. Detached “objectivity,” which is ultimately a weakness that maintains oppression (Dotson, 2011, 2014), then, is not enough; what is needed is a will for inclusion, compassion, and the power to achieve liberation.
Sixth, feminism requires recognizing that among the most pressing concerns in any society are questions presently relevant about the consequences of particular causes (cf. hooks, 2004). At present, the concern with the broadest causal importance to feminism is the matter of understanding and defying oppression in multiple and intersecting forms (hooks, 2000, 2014). So long as many feminists forward individuated personal choice and fail to recognize the importance of intersecting power dynamics and their intrinsic capacity to oppress, they will also fail to realize that entrenched and self-reinforcing dominance in power and the reciprocal docility in subjugation are the exact qualities inherent to all unjust social dynamics. That is, groups that ignore the role of power in generating oppression, of which theirs is but a single part, or that benefit from it and thus refuse to challenge it (Rottenberg, 2014), have no ultimate hope of liberation from it (cf. Collins, 1990). This is the basis of a call to allyship with deep, affective, solidifying roots; without a clear appreciation of oppression, and hence the problem intrinsic to privilege itself—even within feminism itself—there can be no remediation (cf. Ferguson, 2010; Rottenberg, 2017). It is the question of power that is key to understanding culture, and power comes from coalition, and coalition comes from solidarity through allyship (Walters, 2017).
Seventh, the future of a movement that fights oppression is predicated not on its tolerance, particularly of the intolerable, but upon its intolerance of oppression in all its forms. This is Ferguson’s (2010) point. It is best phrased, however, by hooks in Ain’t I a Woman?, where she asks, “how does one overthrow, change, or even challenge a system that you have been taught to admire, to love, to believe in?” (hooks, 2014, p. 121). It is a common but significant error to believe that feminism can be strengthened by merely forming a coalition with some other similar movement (cf. Walters, 2017). It is true that coalitions of this kind result in an increase in the outer dimensions of feminism, and it follows that superficial assessments will render this as an increase in the capacity to effect change. Historically, however, such a coalition usually leads to internal disagreements and inner weakening that will later render it ineffective —for whatever one can say about the similarities in character of two separate movements, it is, in reality, rarely present. Take, for example, the case of the deep struggles between broader feminism and Black feminism that initiated the need for intersectionality, which arose under insufficiently articulated allyship and porosity instead of solidarity in feminism (Collins, 1990; cf. hooks, 2014). If there were solidarity between the movements then there would not be two movements in coalition but only one movement based upon the values and conditions of that solidarity. This is why the core notion for solidarity feminism should be inclusive allyship based on a legitimate apprehension of the harms of oppression in all of its manifestations (Mohanty, 2003; cf. Reicher et al., 2006).
Put differently, the capacity for feminism to effect change is exclusively guaranteed by its ability to achieve inner solidarity through allyship. This is the character of a feminism which does not merely seek early or momentary successes, as are provided by choice feminism (Ferguson, 2010) and under neoliberalism (Rottenberg, 2014), but of a feminism for which the enduring work against oppression is elicited by absolute intolerance to oppression as the root of long-term growth. Superficial allyship for particular aims can only produce a feminism that owes its strength to compromises, which leaves them like plants germinated in a conservatory that then lack the hardening to withstand adverse weather and thus defy history (cf. hooks, 2014). The apparent advantage feminism obtains by forming coalitions on grounds other than inclusive allyship is often undone as maturing factions begin to turn to their own interests (Rottenberg, 2014, 2017).
Eighth, and finally, on principle, feminism must endeavor to present itself so that feminists do not view the oppression of others as remote, as can happen under choice feminism, but as the object of their own endeavors. Ferguson (2010) captured this notion clearly and articulated it in her imperative to judiciousness of concern and identification between the personal and the political. That is, oppression is not something feminists should avoid; it is the bedrock upon which feminism is grounded. Part of this work demands feminists not fear criticism and outrage that can follow from challenging privileged systems (cf. Bailey, 2014, 2017; Dotson, 2014). Instead, we must look for these signs, heed Ferguson’s admonition not to fear the political, and recognize them as forms of privilege-preserving pushback (Bailey, 2017) and fragility (cf. DiAngelo, 2011).
Feminism and Solidarity
Because of the real and material barriers that prevent many from taking such risks, it may go too far to say that any feminist who is not reproached by more privileged detractors, who is not subject to censures for her contributions, may be shortchanging her feminism. Still, for activists, among the best measures for the impact of one’s feminism—for the sincerity of allyship, the conviction to the cause against oppression, and the force of solidarity and (good)will behind it—is evoking the privilege-preserving hostility, pushback, and outrage from positions of privilege (Bailey, 2014, 2017; DiAngelo, 2011; Dotson, 2011, 2014). Dominance and oppression seek to retain their status, power, and dominance over those they oppress, as this is the intrinsic function of privilege upon society (Bailey, 2017; cf. Ferguson, 2010).
Of all the seductions of choice feminism, indulgence and flattery of privilege is the most potent lure away from doing the difficult work against oppression. It therefore must be repeatedly pointed out that privilege always seeks to preserve itself (Bailey, 2014, 2017; Dotson, 2014). Privilege, therefore, always pushes back. This is often through (inadvertent) dishonesty of willful or strategic ignorance (Bailey, 2017; Dotson, 2011), so much so that even the occasional truth that comes out against liberation is mainly intended to cover a greater falsification and thus acts a tool of untruth or epistemic exclusion/oppression (Dotson, 2014). Privilege can therefore lead people to be unwitting masters in deception, especially of themselves, and so we all inadvertently perpetuate privilege. Consequently, every assertion of privilege made against a feminist standing in solidarity against oppression—especially every misrepresentation made against the unmaking of oppression and dominance—can be interpreted a mark of honor upon she who stands in solidarity. This is because privileged fragility will always fight the loss of privilege and dismantling of oppressions, and thus receiving its opprobrium, when it can be done, means one’s solidarity was effective. And every such act of solidarity against privileged domination carries with it the diminution of oppression.
For Ferguson (2010), then, this requires a willingness to enjoy the sacrifices of one’s feminism (cf. Friedman, 2003, p. 71); for Rottenberg (2014) it is an imperative to relinquish the selfishness inherent in a “happiness project,” posing as neoliberal feminism, possible only for the most privileged women. Ferguson asks the requisite hard questions of feminists committed to allyship, ultimately encouraging them to learn to love the emancipatory struggle for what it more deeply represents:
However, if we suspend judgment in the context of our personal relationships, we seem to be failing in courage as feminists—for feminism is precisely about reimagining and reworking the personal… Our political views also exact a demanding standard for ourselves… It can be exhausting to subject our every thought, our every decision to feminist analysis. (Ferguson, 2010, p. 249)
Understandably, though not quite forgivably, this is not widely considered desirable within choice feminism or feminism maintained under neoliberal aims. As noted by Ferguson, “As long as feminism provokes these criticisms, some feminists will be tempted to adopt some kind of a choice feminist orientation in response… Choice feminism will continue to have broad appeal to feminists because it gives us an easy way out of the dilemmas of politicizing the personal” (2010, pp. 249–250). Identical issues exist within neoliberal feminism for the same reason—an abnegation of responsibility against oppression. As explained by Rottenberg (2014, p. 432), neoliberal feminism, like choice feminism, is “No longer concerned with issues, such as the gendered wage gap, sexual harassment, rape or domestic violence, ambitious individual middle-class women themselves become both the problem and the solution in the neoliberal feminist age” (p. 432). Why? Because it doesn’t need to be; hence the demand for allyship as a solidarity capable of producing a genuinely liberatory feminism.
In conclusion, the call for feminism is a call to allyship and internal solidarity to stand against privilege, oppression, and dominance in all its forms. It is for feminism to recognize the moral worth and practical strength of allyship and solidarity, then, and to step away from narrower concerns that manifest under choice feminism and in service to neoliberalism that masquerades as “feminism.” Once an oppressed group earns access to privilege and chooses to enjoy and multiply it rather than continue to fight on behalf of others who are more oppressed, as many women have done after choice feminism took root, it loses the best part of its power. There is a moral potency in standing in solidarity on the side of anti-oppression. It is sold on the veneration of privilege. There is both strength and duty in allying through values of inclusion and anti-oppression with those who suffer distress, disgrace, slavery, and compulsion. Feminism’s charge is to find allyship by looking at oppression wherever it arises. We should hold out our hands to each other, and may those who are too proud, privileged, or ashamed to take them recognize the cost of their choices and reconsider their commitments.
References
Bailey, A. (2014). The unlevel knowing field: An engagement with Dotson’s third-order epistemic oppression. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 3(10), 62–68.
Bailey, A. (2017). Tracking privilege-preserving epistemic pushback in feminist and critical race philosophy classes. Hypatia, 32(4), 876–82.
Banet-Weiser, S. (2015). ‘‘Confidence you can carry!”: Girls in Crisis and the Market for Girls’ Empowerment Organizations. Journal of Media & Cultural Studies, 29(2), 182–193.
Bay-Cheng, L. Y. (2012). Recovering empowerment: De-personalizing and re-politicizing adolescent female sexuality. Sex Roles, 66(11–12), 713–717.
Boucher, L. (2017). Radical Visions, Structural Constraints: Challenges to Anti-Oppressive Practice in Feminist Organizations. Affilia, 33(1), 24–38.
Brooks, A. (1997). Postfeminisms: Feminism, Cultural Theory and Cultural Forms. New York: Routledge.
Carbin, M., & Edenheim, S. (2013). The intersectional turn in feminist theory: A dream of a common language? European Journal of Women’s Studies, 20(3), 233–248.
Collins, P. H. (1990). Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment. New York: Routledge.
Cudd, A. E. (2006). Analyzing oppression. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Davis, K. (2008). Intersectionality as a buzzword: A sociology of science perspective on what makes a feminist theory successful. Feminist Theory, 9(1), 67–85.
Dhamoon, R. K. (2010). Considerations on mainstreaming intersectionality. Political Research Quarterly, 64(1), 230–243.
DiAngelo, R. (2011). White Fragility. The International Journal of Critical Pedagogy, 3(3), 54–70.
Dotson, K. (2011). Tracking epistemic violence, tracking practices of silencing. Hypatia, 26(2), 236–257.
Doston, K. (2014). Conceptualizing epistemic oppression. Social Epistemology, 28(2), 115–138.
Edwards, K. E. (2006). Aspiring social justice ally identity development: A conceptual model. NASPA Journal, 43(4), 39–60.
Featherstone, M. (1996). Consumer culture and postmodernism. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Ferguson, M. (2010). Choice feminism and the fear of politics. Perspectives on Politics, 8(1), 247–253.
Foucault, M. (2008). The history of sexuality: The will to knowledge. New York: Penguin.
Frieden, B. (1963). The feminine mystique. New York: Norton.
Friedman, M. (2003). Autonomy, gender, politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Genz, S. (2006). Third Way/ve: The politics of postfeminism. Feminist Theory, 7(3), 333–353.
Gibson, P. A. (2014). Extending the Ally Model of social justice to social work pedagogy. Journal of Teaching in Social Work, 34(2), 199–214.
Gill, R. (2016). Post-postfeminism?: New feminist visibilities in postfeminist times. Feminist Media Studies, 16(4), 610–630.
Goodkind, S. (2009). “You can be anything you want, but you have to believe it”: Commercialized feminism in gender-specific programs for girls. Signs, 34(2), 397–422.
Goodkind, S., & Ballentine, K. (2017). Feminist social work and political engagement: Working toward social justice through local policy. Affilia, 32(4), 425–431.
Greenberg, J. (2014). Beyond allyship: Multiracial work to end racism. Tikkun Magazine, 29(1), 11–18.
Hirschmann, N. J. (2010). Choosing betrayal. Perspectives on Politics, 8(1), 271–278.
Hirshman, L. (2005). Homeward bound. The American Prospect, 16(12), 20–26. Retrieved from http://prospect.org/article/homeward-bound-0/
Hirshman, L. (2006). Get to Work: A Manifesto for Women of the World. Viking.
hooks, b. (2000). Feminism is for Everybody: Passionate Politics. Pluto Press.
hooks, b. (2004). Understanding patriarchy. Louisville Anarchist Federation. Retrieved from http://imaginenoborders.org/pdf/zines/UnderstandingPatriarchy.pdf
hooks, b. (2014). Ain’t I a Woman? Black Women and Feminism. Routledge.
Houvouras, S., & Carter, J. S. (2008). The F word: College students’ definitions of a feminist. Sociological Forum, 23(2), 234–256.
Kirkpatrick, J. (2010). Introduction: Selling out? Solidarity and choice in the American Feminist Movement. Perspectives on Politics, 8(1), 241–245.
Marso, L. J. (2010). Feminism’s quest for common desires. Perspectives on Politics, 8(1), 263–269.
McCall, L. (2005). The complexity of intersectionality. Signs, 30(3), 1771–1800.
McRobbie, A. (2015). Notes on the perfect: Competitive feminism in neoliberal times. Australian Feminist Studies, 30(83), 3–20.
Meyers, D. T. (2004). Being yourself: Essays on identity, action, and social life. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Mitchell, E. (2013). A Marxist-feminist critique of intersectionality theory. Retrieved from https://libcom.org/article/i-am-woman-and-human-marxist-feminist-critique-intersectionality-theory-eve-mitchell
Mohanty, C. T. (2003). “Under Western Eyes” revisited: Feminist solidarity through anticapitalist struggles. Signs, 28(2), 499–535.
Mullaly, B. (2009). Challenging oppression and confronting privilege. Ontario: University Press Canada.
Nash, J. C. (2008). Re-thinking intersectionality. Feminist Review, 89(1), 1–15.
Park, Y., Wahab, S., & Bhuyan, R. (2017). Feminism in these dangerous times. Affilia, 32, 5–9.
Patel, V. S. (2011). Moving toward an inclusive model of allyship for racial justice. The Vermont Connection, 32, 78–88.
Reicher, S., Cassidy, C., Wolpert, I., Hopkins, N., & Levine, M. (2006). Saving Bulgaria’s Jews: An analysis of social identity and the mobilisation of social solidarity. European Journal of Social Psychology, 36(1), 49–72.
Rottenberg, C. (2014). The rise of neoliberal feminism. Cultural Studies, 28(3), 418–437.
Rottenberg, C. (2017). Neoliberal feminism and the future of human capital. Signs, 42(2), 329–348.
Russell, G. M., & Bohan, J. S. (2016). Institutional allyship for LGBT equality: Underlying processes and potentials for change. Journal of Social Issues, 72(2), 335–354.
Snyder, R. C. (2008). What is third-wave feminism? A new directions essay. Signs, 34(1), 175–196.
Snyder-Hall, R. C. (2010). Third-wave feminism and the defense of “choice.” Perspectives on Politics, 8(1), 255–261.
Walters, S. D. (2017). In defense of identity politics. Signs, 43(2), 473–488.
Reviewer Comments
A history of relevant communications about the “Feminist Mein Kampf” paper. Note: This paper was submitted to and reviewed by the journal Feminist Theory before it was submitted to the journal that eventually accepted it, Affilia: Journal of Women and Social Work. The reviews below appear in the following order: First review at Affilia, second review at Affilia, acceptance at Affilia, then as an appendix, its treatment at Feminist Theory (which happened first) is included.
Affilia, first decision: June 22, 2018
Dear Dr. Gonzalez:
We have now received all reviews for the Manuscript ID Affilia-18-058 entitled “Allyship Feminism: An Intersectional Reply to Neoliberal and Choice Feminism” that you submitted to the Affilia and the peer-review process is complete. Having carefully considered the reviewers’ comments, we have decided to decline the manuscript in its current form and invite you to revise and resubmit a new version.
The reviewers are supportive of the work and noted its potential to generate important dialogue for social workers and feminist scholars. From our editorial perspective, the concerns they raise are sufficient in scale and scope to preclude an acceptance at this time. The reviewers’ comments included at the bottom of this letter provide clear direction to improve the clarity of key concepts in the paper; reviewer 1 also provided suggestions to improve the paper’s organization. Please be sure that the revised manuscript responds to all of to the issues outlined below.
To revise your manuscript, log into [REDACTED] and enter your Author Center, where you will find your manuscript title listed under “Manuscripts with Decisions.” Under “Actions,” click on “Create a Revision.” Your original manuscript ID number will be appended to denote a revision.
You will be unable to make your revisions on the originally submitted version of the manuscript. Instead, 1) revise your manuscript using a word processing program and save it on your computer; 2) highlight the changes to your manuscript by using the track changes mode in MS Word or by using bold or colored text and upload this file; 3) prepare a clean version of the manuscript (not showing or highlighting changes) and upload this file as well; 4) use the document attached to this email (‘author’s response form’) to detail how you addressed the comments/suggestions provided by the reviewers; 5) delete any redundant files before completing the submission (your original files are available to you when you upload your revised manuscript).
The following three documents are required for your revised manuscript to be considered for review:
· Revised manuscript – showing changes
· Revised manuscript – clean version
· Completed author’s response form
Once your documents are ready for submission, you can upload and submit them through your Author Center. In order to expedite the processing of the revised manuscript, please be as specific as possible in your response to the reviewer(s) feedback.
IMPORTANT: While making revisions to your manuscript please make sure to follow current APA Style guidelines; omit any identifying information (i.e. authors’ names and universities); and stay within the prescribed page limit (e.g. 30 pages for empirical or conceptual articles and 10 pages for in-brief submissions).
Because we are trying to facilitate timely publication of manuscripts submitted to the AFFILIA: Journal of Women and Social Work your revised manuscript is due to be uploaded within four weeks of receiving this notification. We will have to consider your manuscript as a new submission should you miss the deadline to submit. Please contact me immediately if you anticipate needing additional time.
Once again, thank you for submitting your manuscript to the AFFILIA: Journal of Women and Social Work and I look forward to receiving your revision.
Best regards,
[REDACTED]Co-Editor in ChiefAffilia: Journal of Women and Social Work
Comments to the Author
Reviewer #1:
1. This is an interesting paper seeking to further the aims of inclusive feminism by attending to the issue of allyship/solidarity. However I think that there needs to be further clarity on some of the central concepts that the paper addresses. Two these concepts are the term universal- which should not be conflated with universalism or universalization- as these are terms that hold ahistorical baggage of standing in for dominant perceptions of feminism. The author/s therefore have to be careful not to use a universalizing language that assumes that women representing marginalized groups are the ‘other’ feminists. Nor should the aim be to universalize feminism but rather to make feminism inclusionary. The details of where this appear in the paper are cited in the next section. The second conceptual issue that needs a fuller articulation is the notion of allyship versus solidarity. Allyship has been critiqued by anti-racist feminists because of the ‘innocent’ position it appears to take or assumes of the ally. Solidarity has been understood as working across difference because of a recognition that in some way we are all implicated in the oppression of others and therefore should stand in solidarity against it. This paper needs to make these two terms clearer.
Thank you for your review and your comments. Regarding this point, both of these points were integral to helping us clarify the meaning we had intended with the original manuscript. That intent was to encourage feminists to make a clear turn toward solidarity against all oppression, and you are right that universalization is the wrong way to express that. Inclusion is better. Throughout the manuscript, all calls to universalizing feminism have been rephrased to indicate this improved clarity. Likewise, the requested disambiguation between allyship and solidarity was needed and improved the paper. The original intention was that values-based inclusive allyship entailed solidarity, but this needed more theorizing and clarity, which has been incorporated throughout after a much more thorough discussion of allyship and its relationship to and distinction from solidarity. Particularly, three allyship researchers have been added to deeply enrich, nuance, and even problematize aspects of this discussion, these being Keith Edwards (2006), Bob Mullaly (2009), and Priscilla Gibson (2014).
2. The abstract is obscure in terms of delineating the problematic that the author/s wishes to address in the article. The movement from second wave feminism to neo-liberalism and choice feminism is not clear as there have been other waves after the second wave feminism. Also there is a trenchant critique by critical race feminists who do not agree with the dominant characterization of feminist theories using the linear wave analogy (see Collin’s and other critical race feminists work on this). I am also not so sure how you get from Choice feminism to allyship feminism. I know it’s an abstract and therefore needs to be succinct but since allyship feminism is a crucial concept in your paper there should be a sentence defining it.
In light of this comment, the abstract has been rewritten to clarify and account for all of the points raised here. It now reads,
“In the wake of successes often attributed to “second-wave feminism,” the women’s movement, which was already pluralistic, diversified further along lines of individual choice versus collective action, as enabled by new privileges for women that were not universally accessible. As a result, in societies where neoliberalism is dominant, a form of choice feminism developed in some feminists alongside expanding calls for intersectional allyship, inclusion, and solidarity in others. Many scholars, particularly those within the field of social work, have shown that choice feminism is characterized by a number of problematic themes that can, paradoxically, reinforce oppression for marginalized people. Particularly, it can offer a heuristic of choice that is used to justify feminist decisions that benefit a small set of women at the expense of standing in solidarity with others and remediating oppression. This complex problem may benefit from a detailed interrogation of allyship and its attendant repercussions. Consequently, this paper forwards a framework for solidarity feminism—that is, an approach to feminism that centers solidarity against oppression—by favoring inclusive values-based allyship over choice feminism as an intersectional means to address one aspect of the enduring universalism problem within the feminist movement.” (p. 1)
3. Page three in the paragraph that states: “ Intersectionality’s indispensable contribution to feminism problematizes the simplistic notion of women as monolithic entities. For this reason, intersectional feminism has been seen as divisive rather than unifying (cf. McCall, 2005), though this attitude lies in opposition to the capacity intersectionality has to connect across multiple dimensions of lived oppression (Bridges, 2017). (Boucher [2017], for example, discusses the importance of an intersectional approach to social work practice while acknowledging the difficulty of doing so within cohesive organizations for women’s issues [p. 25].)”. I think that the way you set up this dichotomy between intersectionality and cohesive action or intersectionality and divisiveness is problematic. The fact is that there is no universal woman, taking this fact into account does not have to be divisive unless you buy into the dominant narrative of the universal womanhood- I would therefore nuance this argument because otherwise you are sounding like you agree with the opinion of a particular brand of feminists as though that is a universal truth. Situate who are the feminists who have this particular difficulty with intersectionality, Yes, this is helpful. The original intention had been that people outside of feminism tend to view intersectionality as divisive, but clarifying and nuancing here has added texture and depth to the argument. It is the case that feminists mostly have taken on intersectionality, although some (especially Marxist feminists like Eve Mitchell (2013)) have criticized it and others have sought to add clarity and nuance to this discussion. Most useful among these for us has been a paper by Carbin and Edenheim (2013), which not only elucidates and navigates these debates and summarizes the feminists who have particular difficulty with intersectionaity but takes Marxist (and some choice) feminists to task in precisely the way you indicate is needed here. In that sense, the relevant paragraph has been reworded to incorporate these changes and includes these citations, along with Dhamoon’s (2010) summary of challenges to intersectional implementation in the mainstream and Nash’s (2008) clarifications of the heuristic. The relevant paragraph, spanning pp. 3–4, now reads,
“The importance of an intersectional approach built on plurality, self-determination, and non-judgmentalness becomes clear when remembering that not all women have the same experiences of oppression—there is no universal woman. These experiences vary not only in terms of gender, but also race, religion, sexuality, class, ability, and the ways in which those intersect (Collins, 1990). These indispensable contributions to feminism problematize the simplistic notion of women, privilege, and oppression as monolithic entities. For this reason, intersectional feminism has been misunderstood through the dominant lens of universal womanhood within (materialist and Marxist [see Mitchell, 2013]) feminism and more generally from opponents to feminism (cf. Dhamoon, 2010). It is thus unfairly seen as divisive rather than unifying (cf. esp. Carbin & Edenheim, 2013; Davis, 2008; McCall, 2005; Nash, 2008). Ultimately, this attitude lies in opposition to the capacity intersectionality has to connect across multiple dimensions of lived oppression. Boucher (2017, p. 25), for example, discusses the importance of an intersectional approach to social work practice while acknowledging the difficulty of doing so within cohesive organizations for women’s issues.”
4. P4: in the paragraph where you say: “Though I do not seek to defend liberalism per se, I argue that selfishness in choice feminism is a product not of liberalism but of unrecognized privilege accorded those who benefit from neoliberalism” you need to back up this argument. Add a quote from liberal feminists to show how they reinterpreted choice as autonomy and individualistic to choice as relational. Then you don’t have to defend liberal feminism beyond that.
This comment inspired much consideration. Our original intent had merely been to agree with Rottenberg, though we had said we “argue that,” and this has been amended. Further, however, we also added points from liberal feminists such as Ann Cudd, Marilyn Friedman, and Diana Meyers regarding the ways in which choice and autonomy were reinterpreted under liberal feminism and problematized this by quoting Rottenberg on how it opened a door to neoliberalism. Cudd’s understanding of “deformed desire” was particularly useful, and Friedman’s perspectivalism proved useful here and throughout the paper (as she indicates later how it forms a basis for navigating individualistic autonomy in light of the need for collective autonomy). The relevant portion of that paragraph, spanning pp. 4–5, now reads,
“Though we do not seek to defend liberalism per se, we agree with Rottenberg (2014, pp. 421–422) that selfishness in choice feminism is a product not of liberalism but of unrecognized privilege accorded those who benefit from neoliberalism. Though in different ways, liberal feminists such as Ann Cudd (2006), Marilyn Friedman (2003), and Diana Meyers (2004) reinterpreted choice as individualistic and rooted in autonomy, to choice seen as relational. As Friedman wrote, “what counts for autonomy is someone’s perspectival identity, her wants, desires, cares, concerns, values, and commitments” (2003, p. 11). As such, Cudd’s “deformed desire”—in which “the oppressed come to desire that which is oppressive to them…[and] one’s desires turn away from goods and even needs that, absent those conditions, they would want” (2006, p. 181)—is particularly key to a liberal feminist rendering of female/oppressed autonomy as relational. Following Rottenberg (2014, p. 426), these crucial nuances of liberal feminism were “expediently elided,” however, and replaced under neoliberalism and replaced by treating “climbing the power hierarchy…[as] the feminist objective” (emphasis original).”
5. P5: “Ultimately, neoliberalism led intersectional analyses to problematize universalizing approaches to feminism as representing privileged interests ahead of marginalized ones (cf. hooks, 2000, 2014).” I don’t think that is entirely accurate, Crenshaw in the 1980’s was critiquing liberal feminists for not understanding the intersectional nature of oppression…
The relevant portion of the paper has been reworded to clarify that the roots of intersectionality came as such a critique. What is mentioned here is know characterized as an eventual consequence of the awareness generated in feminism by intersectionality. This better aligns the text with the original intention of the original phrasing. The text (on p. 5) now reads,
“Ultimately, these and other issues helped lead intersectional analyses to critique liberal feminists for failing to understand the intersectional nature of oppression (Collins, 1990), which then problematized universalizing approaches to feminism as representing privileged interests ahead of marginalized ones (cf. hooks, 2000, 2014).”
6. Feminist allyship- P8-10- I think you cold do a better job of delineating the arguments that feminists who use the language of solidarity rather than allyship have offered so that when you do finally adopt the term solidarity it is fully defined and differentiated from allyship.
This entire section of the paper received a thorough rewrite in response to this comment. As such, we have indicated the connections and disconnections between allyship and solidarity (particularly drawing upon Brod et al. (2005), Edwards (2006), Gibson (2014), Greenberg (2014), Reicher et al. (2006), and Russell & Bohan (2016) to do so). In such, the limitations and problematics of allyship are now more thoroughly theorized, and allyship itself is characterized more clearly in terms of Edwards’ (2006) three-stage foundational allyship model that underlies Russell & Bohan’s more specific taxonomy and application. Because the changes in this section were so comprehensive, rather than quoting certain passages here, we point primarily to p. 9, which is mostly rewritten to properly theorize and nuance this portion of our discussion.
7. P/10-11- an important point that is missing from this consideration of what is solidarity is the idea that all of us are complicit in oppressing in one form or the other- that is why solidarity works- because in showing solidarity we are not only sacrificing (of course that happens to in the case of giving up our privileges) but more importantly we are acknowledging that our privilege is complicit in another’s oppression in fluid and multiple ways. I don’t see that being reflected in your definition of solidarity-complicity.
By drawing upon Carbin and Edenheim (2013), these points have been incorporated in a theoretically grounded way into the paper. In light of this comment and the previous, in fact, we have decided to retitle our paper and thematic concept as solidarity feminism rather than allyship feminism. Not only does this better accomplish the goals we envisioned by invoking inclusive values-based allyship as a basis for a more cohesive feminist opposition to oppression in all its forms, it better captures our original intent than an inclusive “allyship feminism” could do. Many of these changes are minor shifts in focus throughout the text, and this portion on pp. 10–11 is the most explicit in clarifying this concern, with our appreciation for some of the phrasing:
“Thus, the ideal values to foreground within feminism must be fundamentally inclusive and intersectional (Boucher, 2017). Because we all are complicit in oppression in one form or another, this results in a turn toward solidarity and thus acknowledging that our privileges are complicit in effecting another’s oppressions in fluid and multiple ways (Carbin & Edenheim, 2013). This acknowledgement is, in fact, why solidarity works. Thus, a solidarity feminism rooted in scholarship on allyship, and the complexly interwoven and fluid dynamics of privilege and oppression may provide a needed site for feminist cohesion (Carbin & Edenheim, 2013; McCall, 2005).”
8. p.15- “Put another way, if we feminists had, rather than becoming distracted by seductions of choice, the baubles of neoliberalism, or male approval, implacably guarded the interests of oppressed people—especially those dominated by racism, colonialism, imperialism, ableism, homophobia, classism, and all other manners of oppression that intersect with feminism—and if in matters of remaking society feminists had avowed only their commitment against oppression of all forms with equal intensity as they defended their will to female choice, and if with equal firmness they had demanded emancipation for all those oppressed (cf. hooks, 2000), today we would very likely have equality.” Be careful of the way you use language- this paragraph, like others in your article hearkens to a universal, monolithic we (feminists) who are somehow not from the marginalised groups that you then list- in which case we feminists are presumably white, able-bodies, cis-gendered etc…
The language in this section (now on pp. 20–21) and throughout the paper has been modified to reflect the spirit of this comment. We have been very careful to reconsider much of the phrasing and diction in the paper to avoid such exclusionary totalizing, universalizing, and even implicitly othering language such as this and have adopted a more modest and inclusive tone throughout. These changes are mostly small but very consequential in modifying the tone and position of the paper.
9. P. 16- the goal of justice that you refer to as needing to be single minded is in fact multifarious in its interpretation- no two feminists will have a single minded notion of what justice constitutes. Again you use universalizing language instead of intersectional and pluralistic concepts of feminism and justice.
In line with the previous few comments, the language throughout the paper has been amended to minimize the use of totalizing, universalizing, exclusionary, and othering language (which we had originally included to be, I don’t know, a bit more stirring?). For example, the relevant sentence, now on pp. 21–22, has been reworded as follows:
“Though what constitutes justice is itself multifarious and pluralistic, only a single-minded alignment with solidarity for effecting the goal of justice will suffice (cf. Hirschmann, 2010; hooks, 2000; Patel, 2011; Russell & Bohan, 2016).”
10. p.17- how do you define compassion?
We have included a clear definition for compassion in the way that we mean it, which is as “the awareness of and concern for the suffering and oppression of others, which is the root of solidarity and inclusive values-based allyship (cf. Greenberg, 2014; Patel, 2011; Reicher et al., 2006)” (p. 22).
11. P20- I understand the term universalizing feminism as something that is inclusive for all different types and kinds of women but I still think that the language that uses the term ‘universalizing’ runs into the problem that this word contains historical baggage that intersectional, anti-racist feminists of the likes that you cite in your own paper have critiqued and unpacked.
Almost like the responses to the comments above, we have edited the paper to remove calls for universalizing where we had originally intended calling merely to inclusion and solidarity. Furthermore, universalizing feminism has been problematized slightly more near the beginning of the paper in the portion that reviews extant literature. The original choice of this phrasing was meant to stand in opposition to the claim that choice feminism “universalizes” feminism by making it such that anything a “free” woman does is inherently feminist, but it makes more sense to characterize this in terms of inclusion and solidarity and to avoid the confusion and historical baggage altogether. For instance, the relevant passage that seems to be referred to in this comment (now on p. 24) has been rephrased,
“Take, for example, the case of the deep struggles between broader feminism and Black feminism that initiated the need for intersectionality, which arose under insufficiently articulated allyship and porosity instead of solidarity in feminism (Collins, 1990; cf. hooks, 2014). If there were solidarity between the movements then there would not be two movements in coalition but only one movement based upon the values and conditions of that solidarity. This is why the core notion for solidarity feminism should be inclusive allyship based on a legitimate apprehension of the harms of oppression in all of its manifestations (Mohanty, 2003; cf. Reicher et al., 2006).”
We think these changes are subtle in terms of the language used but significant in terms of the meaning conveyed.
Reviewer #2:
1. Thank you for the opportunity to read and offer comments on Allyship feminism: An intersectional reply to neoliberal and choice feminism. I approached the paper with interest, largely due to some of my own concerns related to neoliberalism and choice feminism, coupled with my ambivalence and caution around the “allyship” frame. As I read your manuscript, I found your framing and treatment of both neoliberal and choice feminisms well grounded. More questions arose for me in the framing of allyship and privilege, calls for a universalizing feminism, and your eight-point path forward for social change. I’ll take up each of these points below.
Thank you for your review. In light of your comments and the comments of the other reviewer, the framing of allyship, privilege, and oppression have been significantly reworked. The concept of “universalizing” feminism has been retooled in terms of inclusion and solidarity, keeping better in line with the original ethos of the paper. (As noted above for the other reviewer: The original choice of this phrasing was meant to stand in opposition to the claim that choice feminism “universalizes” feminism by making it such that anything a “free” woman does is inherently feminist, but it makes more sense to characterize this in terms of inclusion and solidarity and to avoid the confusion and historical baggage altogether.) The eight-point path forward for establishing what is now described as a solidarity feminism (instead of allyship feminism) has seen a major reworking to put it in line with the theorizing of allyship researchers including Keith Edwards (2006), Bob Mullaly (2009), and Priscilla Gibson (2014). More details are presented below in response to your more specific comments.
2. Allyship remains undertheorized in the manuscript as it stands right now. The notion of allyship has come under tremendous scrutiny in recent years – both in the activist and academic literature – particularly due to its potential to be a status claimed by allies whom the populations they claim to ally themselves with do not assign them the same status. Put differently, there are clear power dynamics involved in claiming the title of “ally,” and these do not appear in your manuscript deeply theorized enough. This is particularly true when we fold intersectionality in as a theoretical frame within which to conceptualize allyship. What happens when conflicting interests arise in terms of ally behavior or positionalities, because of the intersectional power relationships that may unfold? Does any feminist ever hold just one position from which to offer allyship?
This entire section of the paper received a thorough rewrite in response to this comment (and a similar one from the other reviewer – see above, Comment 6). As such, we have indicated the connections and disconnections between allyship and solidarity (particularly drawing upon Brod et al. (2005), Edwards (2006), Gibson (2014), Greenberg (2014), Reicher et al. (2006), and Russell & Bohan (2016) to do so). In such, the limitations and problematics of allyship are now more thoroughly theorized, and allyship itself is characterized more clearly in terms of Edwards’ (2006) three-stage foundational allyship model that underlies Russell & Bohan’s more specific taxonomy and application. We have, particularly, acknowledged and problematized the power dynamics inherent in the allyship relationship and shifted focus toward inclusion and solidarity because of the problematics inherent to the multifarious nature of intersectional concerns and problematics contained therein. The entire section received substantive nuancing and theorizing, and this shows up most throughly on p. 9 of the revised manuscript.
3. Similar arguments arose for me in your discussion of privilege; both privilege and oppression emerge in the paper as totalizing and unexamined experiences (even inasmuch as you invoke intersectionality), and there appears to be a default expectation that the feminist reading your paper is coming from privileged positionalities (largely, if not exclusively). Consequently, the oppressed “other” remains othered in the paper, and the default feminist ally remains positioned in the center of your argument.
This is an excellent point. In response, we have attempted throughout the paper to make necessary small changes that minimize references to “the privileged” and “the oppressed” as something like monolithic, totalizing classes, and much nuance has been included about the intersectional nature of oppression. This was particularly addressed when indicating that the effective underpinning for solidarity is, in fact, that it contains the inherent recognition and acknowledgement that we all participate in one another’s oppression in varying ways, often as a result of our (underexamined) privileges. Certainly our intent hadn’t been to mischaracterize those suffering under varying forms of oppression through a totalizing “the oppressed” that further others them from “the privileged,” so the phrasing throughout has been changed accordingly. As the original intent of “allyship feminism” (now solidarity feminism) had been for every feminist to recognize herself as an “ally” to every other feminist and all who suffer under oppressions of any kind, we are glad to have had it brought to our awareness that the phrasing had inadvertently centered a default feminist ally (imagined as one with significant privilege and thus other to “the oppressed” with whom she allies herself).
Additionally, as a result of this comment, some others, and some made by the other reviewer, the concept of allyship itself has been significantly nuanced and problematized. By recognizing especially the capacity for an ally to claim or utilize a privileged status over those she considered herself allied with, there is immediately at least a threat of tokenizing, exploitation, and the (re)production of power dynamics, and this is now thoroughly accounted for up-front in the theoretical review. By problematizing and limiting allyship and shifting the focus to solidarity, which has been disambiguated from allyship, we feel we have adjusted the focus throughout to amend the previously problematic descriptions.
For two examples of this renuancing of the paper in terms of privilege and oppression, consider from pp. 10–11, “What brings reforms to fruition is a movement that can stand up and “think together,” as Rosalind Gill (2016) phrased it—and thus create change in terms of transformative ideas. There may be no “universal woman” to define a one true feminism, and under intersectional heuristics neither privilege nor oppression can be regarded as totalizing, but standing in solidarity against oppression in all its forms is one such transformative idea.” and from further down p. 11, “This discontent is manifest in many ways, and only some of these are reified as feminist and then lauded under neoliberal and choice feminism (Ferguson, 2010); this appears to be the case despite the way in which such disunity “hollows out the potential” for collective feminist reform (Rottenberg, 2014, p. 420). We all have our privilege and our oppression, however.”
4. Concrete examples of this appear on: 1) p12, in your discussion of special feminists who reject privilege: how do they reject privilege? Is this even possible?
We apologize for the unclear phrasing and have reworded the relevant section to reflect our original intention, which meant to convey the idea that they reject the belief that their privilege is just “part of how it is” and is to be accepted as such, as often happens in unexamined privilege. It now appears spanning the divide between pp. 13–14, and reads,
“They reject the belief that their privilege is “just so” and therefore actively refuse the promotion of privileged interests for themselves; meanwhile, with what privilege they have, they work inclusively on behalf of marginalized groups outside their own (Carbin & Edenheim, 2013, esp. p. 245). These are feminists who understand Patel’s (2011) call for inclusive allyship and enact it by being “philosophically committed” to social justice (Edwards, 2006).”
5. And 2) p23-24, where you mention that “every assertion of privilege” should be “interpreted as a mark of honor” but do not expand on the function or purpose of these assertions. In both cases, the feminist is positioned solely as privileged ally to the oppressed, and their privilege remains largely atheoretical and unexamined.
The relevant paragraph has been revised to include a clearer explanation of what was originally meant and of why this is justified. The passage had meant to convey that when members of more dominant groups lash out in privilege-preserving epistemic pushback or out of privileged fragility (cf. DiAngelo, 2011) against a feminist who stands in solidarity against oppressions, that should be taken as a sign that her solidarity was effective and that the expressions of privilege she is opposing are being disrupted. The most relevant portion, now spanning pp. 25 – 26, has been revised to read,
“The privileged can therefore be unwitting masters in deception, especially of themselves, and so we all inadvertently perpetuate privilege. Consequently, every assertion of privilege made against a feminist standing in solidarity against oppression—especially every misrepresentation made against the unmaking of oppression and dominance—can be interpreted a mark of honor upon she who stands in solidarity. This is because privileged fragility will always fight the loss of privilege and dismantling of oppressions, and thus receiving its opprobrium, when it can be done, means one’s solidarity was effective. And every such act of solidarity against privileged domination carries with it the diminution of oppression.”
6. I’m also curious about your use of “universalizing” feminism. While you weave this idea throughout the manuscript, presented as the goal of feminism in general, I find that I don’t understand: 1) the idea itself; or 2) how it came to be the sole goal of feminism. Much more attention needs to be devoted to unpacking this concept and tracing some of your thinking in support of the idea that it’s the foundational goal.
As noted in responses to the other reviewer (especially Comment 11), we have edited the paper to remove calls for universalizing feminism. We used that notion where we had originally intended calling merely to inclusion and solidarity. Furthermore, universalizing feminism has been problematized slightly more near the beginning of the paper in the portion that reviews extant literature (p. 3). The relevant portion of the text on p. 3 now reads,
“This indicates that the problem of universalizing feminism is that it has been the wrong approach all along; feminism should seek inclusion of all marginalized groups and solidarity against oppression—not universality, which has often stood as a de facto proxy for privileging the dominant conception of feminism and urging all marginalized “sisters” to “get in line.” Therefore, while Synder-Hall’s defense of choice feminism at the individualistic level is problematic, her advocacy of pluralism becomes a much stronger argument when considered in an intersectional light (cf. Edwards, 2006, p. 54).”
The original choice of this phrasing was meant to stand in opposition to the claim that choice feminism “universalizes” feminism by making it such that anything a “free” woman does is inherently feminist, but it makes more sense to characterize this in terms of inclusion and solidarity and to avoid the confusion and historical baggage altogether. In particular, the theorizing about intersectionality (and criticism of feminists who see it as divisive) done by Carbin and Edenheim (2013) and a deeper consideration of Russell & Bohan (2016) and Greenberg (2014) was useful in clarifying this distinction for us, and we have incorporated them by citation several times as such.
7. Finally, I’m curious from a methods/procedure standpoint, how you identified your eight-point framework for moving forward in a justice-oriented feminism. Lacking clarity around this, the eight-point path seemed to me too atheoretical and distant from some of the questions that would actually strengthen it.
Thank you for this comment. This led us to investigate allyship and solidarity models as they apply in feminism, movement activism, and social work more deeply. We reorganized the eight points so that they are structured in accordance with a theoretical model that begins with Edwards (2006), who identifies a three-stage model of allyship development from self-interest (e.g., relationship allyship) through guilt to philosophical commitment to social justice (values-based allyship). It also draws upon Gibson’s (2014) approach to applying the Ally Model to social work pedagogy. Gibson’s approach, which also relies upon Edwards (2006) and the practical applications explored by Mullaly (2009), identifies three domains in which allyship is salient (further refined into fifteen characteristics), and it provides practical means by which they can be effected within social work praxis. Considerations of Edwards (2006), Mullaly (2009), and Gibson (2014), then, led me to re-order and modify the eight-point framework I had suggested to be more in line with existing theoretical models of allyship and solidarity.
Particularly, the eight points have been reordered so that they follow a conceptual model drawn from and extending the existing literature. Specifically, what was points 1–8 are now in the following order: 5, 1, 6, 2, 3, 4, 7, 8 in the revised version. This approach addresses the concern of self-interest first (cf. Edwards, 2006), then awareness (cf. Gibson, 2014), then attitudes, beliefs (Gibson, 2014), and guilt (Edwards, 2006), and then addresses principles (Edwards, 2006) and reminds the reader of the limitations of problematics even of such an approach. These themes are woven into the individual points and follow the overarching framework as well. This exploration provided much needed clarity.
8. For instance, your conversation (pp15-16) about risk, choice, and sacrifice seems overly straightforward and simplistic, without adequate attention to the real and material barriers feminists and others may face, and which may limit their allyship and activism. This is an important point, and the issues of these real and material barriers that feminists and others face have been incorporated and acknowledged in the paper. It also adds specificity that the problem we are criticizing is neoliberal/choice feminism. One specific point at which this was incorporated, among other smaller acknowledgements, is on p. 20, which now reads,
“Second, then, in creating solidarity for overcoming oppression, sacrifices will be necessary, and, though we must remain aware of the real and material barriers feminists and others may face that limit their potential for activism, no accessible sacrifice that abnegates neoliberalism should be considered too great”
9. Similarly, on p16 you make allusions to allyship feminism being characterized in some way by an all-or-nothing orientation that I’d like to hear more about. Do you reject incrementalism altogether? Where does this assertion come from, and what are its implications?
Again, we have to apologize for a lack of clarity in our earlier draft and with appreciation for comments that improve it. The original intention was another (veiled?) critique of choice feminism, and the implication about “half-measures” had been intended in that light. Specifically, it had meant to indicate that taking half-measures toward solidarity (in favor of more choice) is the particular problematic that prevents a solidarity feminism from already existing (as many, if not most, feminists generally agree with solidarity in some form). The paper has been reworded to improve the clarity here, and a specific indication that progress will and should be incremental in many regards has been added to remove all doubt. Specifically, the relevant portion of the text, now at the bottom of p. 21, includes,
“Fifth, though change may come in stages, feminism cannot limit itself to half-measures in solidarity or be selfish. These manifest under choice feminism (Ferguson, 2010), for example, by placing emphasis upon a so-called objective standpoint (cf. hooks, 2000, p. 8) or through pursuit of aims that appear feminist but actually support neoliberalism (Rottenberg, 2014, 2017).”
10. Overall, the paper reads to me as a comment or an editorial and might find a better fit in one of those categories than as a conventional article. It’s well grounded in literature, to be sure, but particularly the eight-point path reads more as the author’s editorial stance than a recommendation coming from a deliberate and documented analytic process as would be more conventional in an article.
See response to Comment 7 above. By reorganizing the eight-point framework along the theoretical guidelines of Edwards (2006) and Gibson (2014), we now have situated it within a theoretical approach and made it less editorial in style.
Affilia, second decision: August 17, 2018
Dear Dr. Gonzalez:
Manuscript ID Affilia-18-058.R1 entitled “Our Struggle Is My Struggle: Solidarity Feminism as an Intersectional Reply to Neoliberal and Choice Feminism” which you submitted to the Affilia: Journal of Women and Social Work, has been reviewed. The comments of the reviewer(s) are included at the bottom of this letter.
The reviewer(s) have been very favorable although there are a few minor outstanding issues to address. Therefore, I invite you to respond to the editorial and reviewer(s)’ comments included at the bottom of
this letter and revise your manuscript quickly so that we can move toward publication.
To revise your manuscript, log into [REDACTED] and enter your Author Center, where you will find your manuscript title listed under “Manuscripts with Decisions.” Under “Actions,” click on “Create a Revision.” Your original manuscript ID number will be appended to denote a revision.
You will be unable to make your revisions on the originally submitted version of the manuscript.
Instead, 1) revise your manuscript using a word processing program and save it on your computer; 2) highlight the changes to your manuscript by using the track changes mode in MS Word or by using bold or colored text and upload this file; 3) prepare a clean version of the manuscript (not showing or highlighting changes) and upload this file as well; 4) use the document attached to this email (‘author’s response form’) to detail how you addressed the comments/suggestions provided by the reviewers; 5) delete any redundant files before completing the submission (your original files are available to you when you upload your revised manuscript).
The following three documents are required for your revised manuscript to be considered for review:
• Revised manuscript – showing changes
• Revised manuscript – clean version
• Completed author’s response form
Once your documents are ready for submission, you can upload and submit them through your Author Center. In order to expedite the processing of the revised manuscript, please be as specific as possible in your response to the reviewer(s) feedback.
IMPORTANT: While making revisions to your manuscript please make sure to follow current APA Style guidelines; omit any identifying information (i.e. authors’ names and universities); and stay within the prescribed page limit (e.g. 30 pages for empirical or conceptual articles and 10 pages for in-brief submissions).
Once again, thank you for submitting your manuscript to the AFFILIA: Journal of Women and Social Work and I look forward to receiving your revisions.
Best regards,
[REDACTED]Co-Editor in ChiefAffilia: Journal of Women and Social Work
Comments to the Author
Reviewer #1:
It was a pleasure to reread this article in its current state. I have seldom had the joy of working with a revision in which the reviewers’ feedback was so diligently and thoughtfully attended. As I read the manuscript parallel to your comments on my own and the other reviewer’s notes, I was struck by the depth of thought and time you spent genuinely considering the concerns we raised. The result is a manuscript that, in my mind, makes a genuine and valuable contribution to the conversation and is much better grounded now in a broad literature base than it was previously.
In terms of additional revisions, my only strong recommendation at this point is to do one more thorough read of the manuscript, this time watching for those points where your language still allows “privilege” to be a totalizing status. In my mind, this remains a tension in discussions around equity, justice, oppression, privilege, etc.: identifications of people as privileged and oppressed (privileged OR oppressed, actually) reinscribes the idea that these are positioned as binaries and contradicts some of the central tenets of intersectionality. It constructs each as a fixed category and negates an understanding of power as relational, contextual, and shifting. You do well in your revision to name that you don’t want to construct the concepts in this rigid way, but to drive the point home, I’d recommend one more careful read to catch the places where your language trips you up.
Reviewer #2:
thank you for taking into consideration the various comments made by the reviewers and attending to them. this is now a well written, thought provoking paper that i think should be published. i have just a few editorial comments in terms of clarifying some aspects of the paper, but otherwise no other revisions necessary.
Abstract unclear. Articulate the following sentences more clearly:
“In the wake of successes often attributed to “second-wave feminism,” the women’s movement, which was already pluralistic, diversified further along lines of individual choice versus collective action, as enabled by new privileges for women that were not universally accessible. As a result, in societies where neoliberalism is dominant, a form of choice feminism developed in some feminists alongside expanding calls for intersectional allyship, inclusion, and solidarity in others”.
P. 4 Line 12-20 elaborate unclear as it reads now: “For this reason, intersectional feminism has sometimes been misunderstood through the dominant lens of universal womanhood within (materialist and Marxist [see Mitchell, 2013]) feminism and more generally from opponents to feminism (cf. Dhamoon, 2010). It is thus unfairly seen as divisive rather than unifying (cf. esp. Carbin & Edenheim, 2013; Davis, 2008; McCall, 2005; Nash, 2008).”
P. 6 line 27 onwards- also should be written more clearly and directly.
otherwise a really good paper
Editorial Comments:
1) p. 27, line 16. Consider rewriting the phrase “as have many women as choice feminism took root”, to clarify. The wording is a bit awkward.
2) In addition to the reviewers comments above, please edit the manuscript to follow the APA 6th Edition Style Guide. I’ve noted some instances that need editing below (but not all).
– P. 2 first paragraph and throughout; indent the first line for each next section and paragraph.
– p. 2, first quote from Hirshman is missing a page number.
– p. 2, line 18. page number for quote from Syner-Hall should appear at the end of the sentence. The year does appear after the name.
– p. 2, line 27, for the reference to Ferguson insert the date just after the name.
– p. 3, lines 29-32. The quote that begins with “made to work on behalf” is missing a citation and page number.
– p. 3 line 32. Move (cf. Snyder, 2008) to the end of the sentence.
– p. 5, second paragraph. Long quote from Rottenberg should be indented.
– p. 9, line 9, remove the second parenthesis for (Edwards, 2006, p. 54); cf. Mullaly, 2009).
– p. 10, lines 21-37. Is this quote also attributed to Russell & Bohan, 2016?
Acceptance by Affilia: August 21, 2018
Dear Dr. Gonzalez:
We are pleased to inform you that your manuscript entitled “Our Struggle Is My Struggle: Solidarity Feminism as an Intersectional Reply to Neoliberal and Choice Feminism” has been accepted for publication in Affilia: Women and Social Work.
In order to publish your article, SAGE Publishing requires that you submit a contributor form online. A link to the contributor form, and instructions on how to complete it, will be provided to you via a second email. Please ensure that you do this at your earliest convenience in order to avoid unnecessary delays in the publication of your manuscript.
Once your contributor form is completed, your manuscript will be sent to SAGE for copyediting. You will receive production proofs from SAGE with an opportunity to make any final changes to your manuscript before it is published. Manuscripts are published first at Affilia’s OnlineFirst page before they are assigned to one of our quarterly print issues. Information on publication dates and acceptance dates can be found on the OnlineFirst page: [REDACTED].
On behalf of the Editors of Affilia: Women and Social Work, we would like to thank you for your contribution.
Best Regards,
[REDACTED], PhDEditor in Chief [REDACTED], PhD
Co-editor in Chief
APPENDIX – Feminist Theory review
21-Mar-2018
Dear Dr. Gonzalez:
FT-18-0015 entitled ““While Any Woman is Unfree”: Allyship Feminism as an Intersectional Reply to Neoliberal and Choice Feminism”
Thank you for submitting your article to Feminist Theory.
Unfortunately our reviewers did not feel that this piece was suitable for publication in Feminist Theory.
We attach the reviewers’ comments below in order to help you to revise the piece for submission elsewhere.
We hope that you still consider Feminist Theory when looking to place your work in the future.
Best wishes,
[REDACTED]Feminist Theory Admin AssistantFeminist Theory Journal
[REDACTED]
@FeministTheory
2016 Impact Factor – 1.268
Reviewer(s)’ Comments to Author:
Reviewer: 1
This article juxtaposes choice or neoliberal feminism with allyship feminism, and offers the latter as a means for forming a unified, collective, and universal feminism. The problem of fragmentation in the feminist movement is a longstanding issue in both activist and academic feminist circles. In choosing such a longstanding yet unresolved question, the manuscript is tackling a highly contentious and challenging problem. I am very sympathetic to the core arguments of the paper, such as the need for solidarity and the problematic nature of neoliberal feminism. It is an interesting and passionately written piece, but it fails to meet its defined goals due to a lack of conceptual precision, argumentative rigour, and inaccurate claims, as I explain below.
Framing.
I find it problematic that the paper is premised on false characterisation about the feminist movement as fractured between choice/neoliberal feminism on the one hand, and intersectional allyship on the other. First, the abstract makes a somewhat misleading claim in the abstract that the feminist movement has become fragmented since the second-wave. It was arguably already fragmented then (think of the debates between women’s lib, socialist, radical, and black feminists), and for most scholars, more recent observations of fragmentation have been related more to the emergence of queer, postcolonial, black and intersectional feminism. On page 13, the author writes that feminism as ‘been torn into several parts’ by internal disagreements, citing celebrity and neoliberal feminism a ‘the smallest’ of these parts. Indeed, the rest of the feminist movement has been fairly unified in exposing it as a shallow and individualistic strain of feminism. But, if they are so marginal, why does the article treat them a major group in feminism against which allyship feminism must fight? The paper risks making a strawman out of neoliberal/choice feminism as the central divisive factor preventing the realisation of collective feminist solidarity today, when I have yet to see evidence in the paper that it is neoliberal feminism that is pitting women against each other.
This is additionally problematic because the author uses the juxtaposition of neoliberal and allyship feminism to build a dichotomy of ‘good’ and ‘bad’ feminism that overdetermines the subsequent analysis. For instance, on pages 13-14, the reader is offered two types of feminists: celebrity feminists that are primarily neoliberal feminists, and (presumably) allyship feminists ‘whose views are more broadly aware of the full scope of oppression and dominance’. Again, I am not convinced that this division is representative of the actual divisions in either the feminist movement or feminist theory.
Allyship
a) What is the added value of the concept of allyship? To play the devil’s advocate, surely most feminisms would adhere to this kind of ethical standpoint – that ‘they reject privilege and therefore actively refuse the promotion of privileged interests for themselves; meanwhile they work on behalf of marginalised groups other than just their own’?
b) The paper also needs a critical engagement with the concept of an ally. How does the author understand the relationships between selves, others, and interests? If an ally implies supporting interests that are not ‘one’s own,’ this implies some foundationalist view of the subject where one’s interests are assumed to be tied to subjectivity. For example, is a feminist man a feminist ally or a feminist? Is an anti-racist white woman an ally to black feminists, or an anti-racist feminist? Or both? And if she can be both, why not simply advocate for an anti-racist feminism rather than allyship? Can allyship be problematic? For example, could it reduce white feminist support for WOC into empty statements of allyship, rather than articulate political beliefs and agendas on the basis of feminist anti-racism?
c) When the paper speaks of allyship, is the author referring to allyship within feminism or across other social movements? I ask this because sometimes it is unclear e.g. on page 9, the article seems to broaden its scope beyond feminism to ‘various anti-oppression movements’ that can only achieve their goals ‘through unification’, and again on page 15 mentioning ‘feminism’s ability to link arms with co-constituted anti-oppression movements’.
d) I wonder if this article has an unconscious and unarticulated normative assumption that this allyship should be organised around the assumptions of liberal feminism? After all it argues that allyship feminism ‘embraces a universal principle of justice and rights’ which is at the heart of liberal theory. It also calls for ‘universalising feminism’, though the meaning of this is again unclear (is it the universal embrace of feminism by all people? If so, which feminism?).
e) I wonder to what extent the concept of allyship feminism here struggles to rid itself of the individualism that the article tries hard to disavow. For instance, allyship is defined at one point as ‘support’ of the marginalised by more privileged people (p.6), which translates into ‘a means by which compassion can be directed toward oppressed others’ (p.18). Given its focus on the self, what are its limitations and is something else needed to maintain a collective focus?
f) There is also the question of how well universalisation sits with the idea of allyship, which is aligned here with intersectionality. Allyship assumes that there are separate albeit intersecting subject positions that not all people share, hence the need to show solidarity. Yet, universalism assumes sameness or at least the adoption or development of it, while allyship holds on to difference. This seems like a key tension to address.
g) What is the difference between allyship and structural allyship (p.15)?
Privilege
The paper also has an undefined use of the term privilege. Does it mean the people with more power and/or wealth? It seems to be related to neoliberalism in some way, but it is unclear how, other than that neoliberalism upholds the privileges of the privileged. For instance, on page 4 it somewhat confusingly states that ‘Selfishness in choice feminism is a product not of liberalism but of unrecognised privilege; that is, it is neoliberalism’. How is neoliberalism unrecognised privilege?
Neoliberalism
How does the author understand neoliberalism? Is it meant as an ideology, a set of policies, or a rationality?
Feminist solidarity
a) While I appreciate the article’s attempt to construct a fruitful basis for feminist solidarity, the section on it (p.16 onwards) is often too polemical at the expense of careful argument. For instance, the argument that ‘sacrifices will be necessary and no sacrifice that abnegates feminism should be considered too great’ – is perhaps a bit too exaggerative for an academic text. On page 17 the author also claims that if only ‘feminist had avowed their commitment against oppression of all forms… today we would very likely have equality’. This is a pretty strong assumption to make and assumes that it is simply feminist determination rather than e.g. capitalist structures that prevent the realisation of equality.
b) The paper may be contradicting itself on page 15, first claiming that more privileged feminists must ‘put aside their personal interests and accept adversity’ (lines 25-27), then later down the page it is argued that ‘deeply rooted oppression can only be overthrown by strategically setting such conflicts aside with a single feminist identity bound by structural allyship’ (lines 55-58). Accepting adversity and setting conflicts aside seem to be two different strategies?
c) What is are the values that an ‘inclusive values-based approach’ (p.8) might entail? The same paragraph states that ‘overcoming oppression’ is the ‘operative value for feminism’. Does this mean this should be the value around which values-based allyship feminism should be organised? If so, what if feminists disagree on what entails oppression and how it is caused? How to reconcile e.g. socialist feminism that sees economic relations as the origin of women’s oppression, and those of liberal feminism that focuses on legal reform? For the former, an embrace of ‘universal justice and rights’ is unsatisfactory as these are seen as merely reformist attempts to quell resistance against capital.
Inaccuracies and misrepresentations
a) The paper often slightly misrepresents the authors and discussions that it cites. For instance, Rottenberg is cited as claiming that liberalism sought to ‘overthrow its oppressions’ (p.5), which is not only factually incorrect but misrepresents what Rottenberg (2014: 419) actually says, which is that liberalism was an internal critique of classical liberalism’s gendered exclusions (therefore seeking inclusion and recognition rather than revolution, which I see as equivalent to calls to ‘overthrow’ something). I would also add that no page numbers are given in the paper for this claim, and this is often repeated in the paper when clearly specific passages are being interpreted. Elisabeth Prügl is also mispresented as a defender of neoliberal feminism, which is not (her argument in the 2015 article is that neoliberal feminist policies can sometimes provide openings for positive change as they become invested with bottom-up knowledge and civil society links – she is not defending the rationale of neoliberal feminism). These need to be corrected for reasons of good scholarship.
b) Sometimes the critique of neoliberal feminism could do with a little more nuance. For instance, on page 5 the paper claims that the focus on the balance between work and family life is ‘exclusionary’ to all but white, affluent, able women. I would disagree that this is the main problem, not only because the problem of women’s ‘double burden’ transcends race, class, geographical boundaries. The problem is more specific: that ‘leaning in’ approach is offered as self-help based on assumptions about middle-class women’s career paths in trying to break the class ceiling. In this sense, yes, it assumes feminist subjects that are most likely white, educated and wealthy. But, arguably this logic does neither middle nor working class women any favours: it leaves all women to their own devices in the face of workplace discrimination and care responsibilities (except those few who can afford childcare). It pushes all classes of women to take on a neoliberal ethos of self-care and self-responsibilisation as a means of self-betterment. Most all, it offers neither structural explanations nor collective solutions for women’s oppression for any women.
c) It is not immediately clear to me how neoliberal feminism marginalises LGBT communities by default. While there are cases about the heteronormativity of many neoliberal feminist texts, queer studies have shown that gay lives are just as available to neoliberal co-optation and commodification as those of straight women (e.g. ‘pink money’). Many neoliberal/celebrity feminists seem quite supportive of gay marriage and trans rights, for instance. Finally, it is also not clear how unveiling Muslim women is a neoliberal demand – this is usually a liberal and/or radical feminist argument. In short, the article has to be more careful about not collapsing all oppression as the fault of neoliberalism, even though neoliberal rationality has had a major role in redefining many political issues and questions today.
Additional remarks
The paper argues a lot around the dichotomy of the ‘the oppressed’ and ‘the privileged’. I am not sure whether it is always useful here, especially if employing an intersectional approach that surely complexifies such divisions.
The paper has too many long quotations (both indented and integrated) for instance on pages 10, 11, 12, 18, 26
Odd/unclear sentences
p. 12 ‘feminism cannot be superficial and rest upon the cultural surface; it must grow roots deeply into it’ – culture has not been discussed so it’s unclear where this is coming from and what is being argued.
p.15 First sentence of paragraph 3 (line 32) does not seem to fit the line of argumentation.
p. 16 The first paragraph doesn’t link to the previous paragraph very well and feels repetitive of previous content.
p. 16 Quote on lines 37-41 by Ferguson feels misplaced.
p. 16 ‘Feminism can be universalised internally first’ (line 53) – what does this mean?
Reviewer: 2
While I am extremely sympathetic to this article’s argument and its political positioning, I am afraid that I cannot recommend publication in its current form. The article basically underscores the problematic with so-called choice feminism and neoliberal feminism, while offering a normative vision of where feminism needs to go, namely, an inclusive, value-based allyship feminism. The major problem, however, with this article is that it reads more like a feminist manifesto than an academic article with an innovative, well-argued conceptual and original claim. In fact, a large bulk of the paper is made up of eight points that direct readers on how to cultivate allyship feminism. The tone is declarative rather than explanatory or conceptual, and the author repeats its normative claims again and again (often in the words of other scholars): that feminism needs to fight oppression in all of its forms and that only an inclusive value-based allyship feminism will do. Yet, the terms the author uses are not well enough conceptualized to even really grasp what is being argued for.
In other words, not only do I find the declarative and annunciatory tone problematic but there is no real unpacking of the terms. How precisely is oppression being used – for example, how does structural violence fit into the picture? How does the author define privilege (is it something one “has” or is it a position vis-à-vis dominant norms and power relations)? What exactly constitutes allyship and how does it function (since it is not about coalition)? More importantly, perhaps, what are the conditions of possibility of allyship? Compassion seems too simple an explanation, at least to me, particularly given the important work by psychoanalytic-informed feminist scholarship. Compassion does not seem adequate to explain the emergence of new feminist movements, such as Feminism for the 99%, which were as much about anger as compassion. And what does the author do with poststructuralist (and postcolonial feminist) claims about the exclusions and the violence inherent in calls for universalism, unification and moral certainty with respect to justice (Judith Butler, for example)? Invoking intersectionality (again, without really providing an adequate conceptualization) does not adequately remedy these problems. As I see it, these undertheorized notions are linked to the lack of sustained analysis of how the author understands power and dominance.
In addition, there are also all kinds of bizarre (and in my view facile) judgements about selfishness rather than a discussion of the cultural power dynamics involved that facilitate the promotion of “choice” or, alternatively, a discussion of how neoliberalism as a political rationality disarticulates structural inequality. Furthermore and finally, when speaking about the problematics of neoliberal feminism, the author draws way too heavily on a few scholars who have written on choice feminism and neoliberal feminism. Yet there is a vast literature on these new variants of feminism as well as post- feminism, which need to be discussed (at least briefly) in the context of why this individualized feminism becomes the handmaiden to neoliberal rationality. Here I am thinking of Angela McRobbie and Sarah Banet-Weiser most particularly, but there are many more.